Enumeration reducibility
In computablity theory and computational complexity theory, enumeration reducibility is a method of reduction that determines if there is some effective procedure for determining enumerability between sets of natural numbers. An enumeration in the context of e-reducibility is a listing of the elements in a particular set, or collection of items, though not necessarily ordered or complete.
E-reducibility is a form of positive reducibility, meaning that only positive information is processed. Positive information denotes the logic syntax for "and" () and "or" (). The syntax for negation, "not" () is not included or used.
According to Hartley Rogers Jr., an intuitive model that can be used to explain e-reducibility is as follows:
Let sets and be given. Consider a procedure that is determined by a finite set of instructions in the following way. A computation is begun. The computation proceeds algorithmically except that, from time to time, the computing agent may be requested to obtain an “input" integer, and, from time to time the procedure yields an “output” integer. When an input is requested, any integer, or no integer, may be supplied. Assume that when the members of are supplied, in any order whatsoever as inputs, then the computation always eventually yields the set , in some order, as outputs. The order in which the members of appear may vary as the order of inputs varies. (We permit repetitions in the listing of and in the listing of .) If such a procedure exists we say that is enumeration reducible to .[1]
The concept of e-reducibility was first introduced by the results of John Myhill, which concluded that "a set is many-one complete if and only if it is recursively enumerable and its complement is productive".[2] This result extends to e-reducibility as well. E-reducibility was later formally codified by Rogers and his collaborator Richard M. Friedberg in Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik (the predecessor of Mathematical Logic Quarterly) in 1959.[3]
Definitions
In the definitions provided below, let denote the set of natural numbers () and denote subsets of . Let lower case letters and represent numbers and functions from to .
Rogers' informal definition[1]
In addition to his intuitive model, Rogers also provided a concise reformulation to create an informal definition. It reads:
For any is enumeration reducible to if there is an effective procedure for getting an enumeration of from any enumeration of . Thus we write:
which is the standard notation of enumeration reducibility.
Precise definition[4][5]
From Rogers' informal definition, a precise definition can be inferred.
For any if there exists a computably enumerable set such that, for all
In this case, we write that
- via
or that (the enumeration operator) witnesses .
Properties
Equivalence[6]
- If and is considered to be equivalent through enumeration to . Thus we write
- Conversely, if but we write
- Inversely, if and we write
Supremum[5]
- The supremum (least upper bound) of sets and with respect to can be modeled by a symmetric difference equation. This equation accounts for the lack of information with an abstract variable , which is squared due to the intersection (expressed as the symbol; a union.) It is written as
Turing reduction
- A relationship between Turing reducibility, e-reducibility, and the relation "computably enumerable in" can be shown if a set is given different properties by . This codes it in a positive way regardless if positive or negative information is supplied. It is formally expressed as follows:[5]
- is computably enumerable if and only if
Variants
Strong enumeration reducibilities
In addition to e-reducibility, there exist strong versions, the most important one being s-reducibility (named after Robert M. Solovay). S-reducibility states that a computably enumerable real set is s-reducible to another computably enumerable real set if is at least as difficult to be approximated as .[7] This method shows similarity to e-reducibility in that it compares the elements of multiple sets. In addition, the structure of s-degrees have natural analogs in the enumeration degrees.[5]
The reasoning for using s-reducibility is summarized by Omandaze and Sorbi as a result of positive reducibility models being unable to answer certain oracle questions (e.g. an answer to "Is ?" is only given if , and is not true for the inverse.) because they inherently model computational situations where incomplete oracle information is available.[8] This is in contrast from the well-studied Turing reducibility, in which information is captured in both negative and positive values. In addition, T-reducibility uses information that is provided immediately and without delay. A strong reducibility is utilized in order to prevent problems occurring when incomplete information is supplied.
Partial functions
E-reducibility can be defined for partial functions as well. Writing graph , etc., we can define for partial functions :[9]
- graph graph
Kleene's recursion theorem introduces the notion of relative partial recursiveness, which, by means of systems of equations, can demonstrate equivalence through between graphs of partial functions.[10] E-reducibility relates to relative partial recursiveness in the same way that T-reducibility relates to μ-recursiveness.[5]
References
- Shoenfield, J. R. (July 1969). "Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability (Hartley Rogers, Jr.)". SIAM Review. 11 (3): 415–416. doi:10.1137/1011079. ISSN 0036-1445.
- Myhill, John (1961). "Note on degrees of partial functions". Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society. 12 (4): 519–521. doi:10.1090/S0002-9939-1961-0125794-X. ISSN 0002-9939.
- Sacks, Gerald E. (December 1960). "Richard M. Friedberg and Hartley RogersJr., Reducibility and completeness for sets of integers. Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 5 (1959), pp. 117–125". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 25 (4): 362–363. doi:10.2307/2963569. ISSN 0022-4812. JSTOR 2963569.
- Harris, Charles Milton (2006). Enumeration Reducibility and Polynomial Time. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.95.8166.
- Soskova, Alexandra A.; Soskova, Mariya I. (2017), Day, Adam; Fellows, Michael; Greenberg, Noam; Khoussainov, Bakhadyr (eds.), "Enumeration Reducibility and Computable Structure Theory", Computability and Complexity: Essays Dedicated to Rodney G. Downey on the Occasion of His 60th Birthday, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 271–301, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-50062-1_19, ISBN 978-3-319-50062-1, retrieved 2020-12-18
- Case, John (1971-02-01). "Enumeration reducibility and partial degrees". Annals of Mathematical Logic. 2 (4): 419–439. doi:10.1016/0003-4843(71)90003-9. ISSN 0003-4843.
- Zheng, Xizhong; Rettinger, Robert (2004). Chwa, Kyung-Yong; Munro, J. Ian J. (eds.). "On the Extensions of Solovay-Reducibility". Computing and Combinatorics. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer. 3106: 360–369. doi:10.1007/978-3-540-27798-9_39. ISBN 978-3-540-27798-9.
- Omanadze, Roland Sh.; Sorbi, Andrea (2006-10-01). "Strong Enumeration Reducibilities". Archive for Mathematical Logic. 45 (7): 869–912. doi:10.1007/s00153-006-0012-4. ISSN 1432-0665. S2CID 44764613.
- Cooper, S. Barry (1990). Ambos-Spies, Klaus; Müller, Gert H.; Sacks, Gerald E. (eds.). "Enumeration reducibility, nondeterministic computations and relative computability of partial functions". Recursion Theory Week. Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer. 1432: 57–110. doi:10.1007/BFb0086114. ISBN 978-3-540-47142-4.
- Kleene, Stephen Cole, 1909-1994. (1971). Introduction to metamathematics. Groningen: Wolters-Noordhoff Pub. ISBN 0-7204-2103-9. OCLC 768949.CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
Further reading
Introduction to Metamathematics