Cartesian circle

The Cartesian circle is a potential mistake in reasoning attributed to René Descartes.

René Descartes is a prominent French philosopher who wrote Meditations on First Philosophy. The goal of the Meditations is to build a foundation in which we can learn about the sciences and trust the accuracy of existence. Since writing this work Descartes has received many objections and criticisms.

Descartes argues – for example, in the third of his Meditations on First Philosophy – that whatever one clearly and distinctly perceives is true: "I now seem to be able to lay it down as a general rule that whatever I perceive very clearly and distinctly is true." (AT VII 35)[1] He goes on in the same Meditation to argue for the existence of a benevolent God, in order to defeat his skeptical argument in the first Meditation that God might be a deceiver. He then says that without his knowledge of God's existence, none of his knowledge could be certain. The cartesian circle is an objection to Descartes argument. Descartes has many objectors including Antoine Arnauld who poses an objection to Descartes' Truth Rule.

Cartesian Circle Argument

The Cartesian circle is a criticism of the above that takes this form:

  1. Descartes' proof of the reliability of clear and distinct perceptions takes as a premise God's existence as a non-deceiver.
  2. Descartes' proofs of God's existence presuppose the reliability of clear and distinct perceptions.

Thus, Descartes' argument is circular. Descartes is accused of circularity regarding the Truth Rule because it appears that the Truth Rule is contingent on God’s existence.The Truth Rule states whatever I perceive to clearly and distinctly believe to belong to something truly does belong to it. The Truth Rule is contingent on God’s existence. However, we can only know of God’s existence by being able to clearly and distinctly perceive of this. [2] A circular argument is one in which a premise in an argument includes with the argument’s conclusion. The cartesian circle is an error in reasoning, that has made Descartes' argument circular. Descartes is guilty of circular reasoning due to the fact that a premise of his argument is included in the conclusion of his argument because the rule of truth is contingent upon God’s existence.

The rule of truth is contingent on God’s existence. However, we can only know of God’s existence by being able to clearly and distinctly perceive of this. Another worry that arises from Arnauld’s rejection is the worry of how we can ever come to know of the foundational principles that are needed in order to have knowledge. We can only know something through the foundations of knowledge so a question of interest that arises is how does one know the foundations of knowledge. [3]

Descartes' contemporaries

Many commentators, both at the time that Descartes wrote and since, have argued that this involves a circular argument, as he relies upon the principle of clarity and distinctness to argue for the existence of God, and then claims that God is the guarantor of his clear and distinct ideas. The first person to raise this criticism was Marin Mersenne, in the "Second Set of Objections" to the Meditations:

"you are not yet certain of the existence of God, and you say that you are not certain of anything. It follows from this that you do not yet clearly and distinctly know that you are a thinking thing, since, on your own admission, that knowledge depends on the clear knowledge of an existing God; and this you have not proved in the passage where you draw the conclusion that you clearly know what you are." (AT VII 124–125)

Descartes' own response to this criticism, in his "Author's Replies to the Fourth Set of Objections", is first to give what has become known as the Memory response;[4] he points out that in the fifth Meditation (at AT VII 69–70) he did not say that he needed God to guarantee the truth of his clear and distinct ideas, only to guarantee his memory:

"when I said that we can know nothing for certain until we are aware that God exists, I expressly declared that I was speaking only of knowledge of those conclusions which can be recalled when we are no longer attending to the arguments by means of which we deduced them." (AT VII 140)

René Descartes

Secondly, he explicitly denies that the cogito is an inference: "When someone says 'I am thinking, therefore I am, or I exist' he does not deduce existence from thought by means of a syllogism, but recognizes it as something self-evident by a simple intuition of the mind." (AT VII 140) Finally, he points out that the certainty of clear and distinct ideas does not depend upon God's guarantee (AT VII 145–146). The cogito in particular is self-verifying, indubitable, immune to the strongest doubt.

Antoine Arnauld is another one of Descartes objectors. He objected to Descartes' argument regarding what is referred to as The Truth Rule. Arnauld accuses Descartes of circular reasoning. He says Descartes reasons in a circle because according to Descartes since we know that God exists what we clearly and distinctly perceive is true. However, according to Descartes we are certain that God exists because we can clearly and distinctly perceive this. Arnauld states that before we can come to the conclusion of God’s existence we must be sure that whatever we clearly and distinctly perceive is true. In this objection, Arnauld is stating that God’s existence cannot be used to prove that what one clearly and distinctly perceives is true. Another worry that arises from Arnauld’s rejection is the worry of how we can ever come to know of the foundational principles that are needed in order to have knowledge. We can only know something through the foundations of knowledge so a question of interest that arises is how does one know the foundations of knowledge. [3]

Modern commentators

Bernard Williams presents the memory defense as follows: "When one is actually intuiting a given proposition, no doubt can be entertained. So any doubt there can be must be entertained when one is not intuiting the proposition." (p. 206) He goes on to argue: "The trouble with Descartes's system is not that it is circular; nor that there is an illegitimate relation between the proofs of God and the clear and distinct perceptions [...] The trouble is that the proofs of God are invalid and do not convince even when they are supposedly being intuited". (p. 210)

As Andrea Christofidou explains:

"The distinction appropriate here is that between cognitio and scientia; both are true and cannot be contradicted, but the latter is objectively true and certain (with the guarantee of God), while the former is subjectively true and certain, that is, time-bound, and objectively possible (and does not need the guarantee of God)." (pp 219–220)

Another defense of Descartes against the charge of circularity is developed by Harry Frankfurt in his book Demons, Dreamers, and Madmen: the Defense of Reason in Descartes' Meditations (Bobbs–Merrill, 1970; reprinted by Princeton University Press, 2007). Frankfurt suggests that Descartes' arguments for the existence of God, and for the reliability of reason, are not intended to prove that their conclusions are absolutely true, but to show that reason can be compelled to accept them, even in the face of radical skeptical arguments. In fact, according to Frankfurt, the validation of reason is accomplished by the rejection of the main sceptical hypothesis, which is the first real (albeit negative) conclusion of the argument, whilst the proposition about God's existence is a merely preparatory step. It must be conceded that once reached the real conclusion of the argument, the Cartesian method would forbid the sceptic to reply that perhaps the cartesian proof was suggested to the meditator by the evil genius itself, in the first place (thereby accusing Descartes of vicious circularity). This accusation fails, since it requires the evil genius' existence to be still deemed (at least) a possibility – an idea which precisely, after the expanded "God's proof" the meditator has acquired a specific reason to reject.

However, according to Frankfurt the proof presupposes the validity of the principle of non-contradiction, since otherwise an argument leading to the (provisional) conclusion that a benevolent God exists, wouldn't force Descartes to reject the possible existence of the demon. Thus the proof might, after all, beg the question against a kind of skepticism radical enough to put in doubt the rule of non-contradiction.

Moreover, according to Frankfurt's Descartes, the meditator feels forced to accept his conclusion merely because of the evidence of the supporting argument, while Frankfurt himself started by explaining that the radical doubt is meant to be a criticism of evidence as a criterion of truth (even subjective truth, if you want). As Frankfurt pointed out, it seems hard to deny that the general proposition "evident statements can be false or misleading" can be thought without hindrance, and that Descartes seems to have countenanced this kind of doubt, when close to the end of the First Meditation he wrote that

"...as I sometimes think that others are in error respecting matters of which they believe themselves to possess a perfect knowledge, how do I know that I am not also deceived each time I add together two and three, or number the sides of a square, or form some judgment still more simple, if more simple indeed can be imagined?"

The outcome seems to be that a doubt aimed at evident ideas is supposed by Frankfurt to be overcome by means of a further evident idea, thereby begging the question.

See also

Notes

  1. "AT" refers to Oeuvres de Descartes, ed. by Charles Adam and Paul Tannery.
  2. Newman, Lex (1997-12-03). "Descartes' Epistemology". Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  3. Carriero, John (2008-04-15), A Companion to Descartes, Blackwell Publishing Ltd, pp. 302–318, doi:10.1002/9780470696439.ch18, ISBN 978-0-470-69643-9 Missing or empty |title= (help); |chapter= ignored (help)
  4. "The Cartesian Circle". www.owl232.net. Archived from the original on 2017-10-08. Retrieved 2017-10-09.

References

  • René Descartes, The Philosophical Writings of Descartes Volume II, translated John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch (Cambridge University Press, 1984) ISBN 0-521-28808-8
  • Andrea Christofidou, "Descartes' Dualism: Correcting Some Misconceptions" (Journal of the History of Philosophy XXXIX:2, April 2001)
  • Bernard Williams, Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry (Penguin Books, 1978) ISBN 0-14-022006-2
  • Newman, Lex, "Descartes’ Epistemology", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/descartes-epistemology/>.
  • John Carriero, “Cartesian Circle and the Foundations of Knowledge”
  • Gary Hatfield, “The Cartesian Circle,” in Gaukroger, Blackwell Companion to Descartes’ Meditations (2006), pp. 122-141.
This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.