Highest median voting rules

Highest median voting rules are cardinal voting rules, where the winning candidate is a candidate with the highest median rating. As these employ ratings, each voter rates the different candidates on an ordered, numerical or verbal scale.

The various highest median rules differ in their treatment of ties, i.e., the method of ranking the candidates with the same median rating.

Proponents of highest median rules argue that they faithfully reflect the voter's opinion, that they satisfy the independence of irrelevant alternatives and do not fall within the scope of Arrow's impossibility theorem.[1] Critics point out that highest median rules violate the Condorcet criterion: a candidate can in principle be elected even if all voters but one prefer another candidate.[2][3]

Definition and notation

Let be the set of candidates, the set of voters, and an ordered finite set of ratings (e.g. the following ratings: "Very good", "Good", "Average", "Bad").

For any candidate , 's median rating is the median rating among the ratings that received from voters. For example, if there are ten voters and if candidate receives three ratings "Good", six ratings "Average", and one rating "Bad", its median rating is "Average".

If, for any candidate , , then obtained a higher median rating than all other candidates, and is elected, regardless of which highest median rule was chosen.

When different candidates share the same median rating, a tie-breaking rule is required. This tie-breaking rule characterizes the highest median rule at use.

Tie-breaking rules often make use of two additional statistics about a candidate 's ratings:[4]

  • The share of proponents to , noted , which is the share of voters attributing to a rating greater than its median . In the example above, the three ratings "Good" are above 's median "Average", so .
  • The share of opponents to , noted , which is the share of voters attributing to a rating lesser than its median . In the example above, this correspond to the rating "Bad", so .

Examples

Example of vote outcome where each choice (or candidate) A, B, C or D wins according to one of the four tie-breaking rule studied: respectively typical judgment (), central judgment (), usual judgment (), and majority judgment ().[4]
  • The typical judgment orders the candidates according to the largest difference between their share of proponents and opponents, i.e. according to the formula:[4] (the indices are omitted for simplicity). In the above example, and identifying "Average" with the grade , we have .
  • The usual judgment is the rule said to offer the best properties,[4] but it orders the candidates according to a slightly more complex formula: .
  • The central judgment orders the candidates according to the highest ratio between the shares of proponents and opponents, that is to say according to the formula: (where is an arbitrarily small number that simply allows the denominator to remain positive).
  • The majority judgment considers the candidate who is closest to having a rating other than its median and breaks the tie based on that rating. This is equivalent to ordering the candidates according to their score ,[4] defined by the following formula (the symbol denotes the indicator function) : .
  • The Bucklin rules are close to the highest median rules but have been developed for ranked rules. They order the candidates according to the formula: . In a ranked rule, this is equivalent to counting first choice votes first. If one candidate has a majority, that candidate wins. Otherwise the second choices are added to the first choices. If a candidate with a majority vote is found, the winner is the candidate with the most votes accumulated. Lower rankings are added as needed.[5]
  • Approval voting corresponds to the degenerate case where there are only two possible rating: approval and disapproval. In this particular case, all the tie-breaking rules are equivalent, and the Condorcet criterion is satisfied.[6]

See also

References

  1. Balinski, Michel; Laraki, Rida (2007). "A theory of measuring, electing, and ranking". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 104 (21): 8720–8725. doi:10.1073/pnas.0702634104. PMC 1885569. PMID 17496140.
  2. Brams, S. and R. Potthoff (2015) "The paradox of grading systems" http://www.politics.as.nyu.edu/docs/IO/2578/GradingParadox.pdf
  3. Felsenthal, Dan S. and Machover, Moshé, « The Majority Judgement voting procedure: a critical evaluation », Homo oeconomicus, vol 25(3/4), p. 319-334 (2008) http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.324.1143&rep=rep1&type=pdf
  4. Fabre, Adrien (2020). "Tie-breaking the Highest Median: Alternatives to the Majority Judgment" (PDF). Social Choice and Welfare. doi:10.1007/s00355-020-01269-9.CS1 maint: date and year (link)
  5. Collective decisions and voting: the potential for public choice, Nicolaus Tideman, 2006, p. 204
  6. Brams, Steven; Fishburn, Peter (1978). "Approval Voting". American Political Science Review. 72 (3): 831–847. doi:10.2307/1955105. JSTOR 1955105.

Further reading

This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.