Distributive justice

Distributive justice concerns the socially just allocation of resources. Often contrasted with just process, which is concerned with the administration of law, distributive justice concentrates on outcomes. This subject has been given considerable attention in philosophy and the social sciences.

In social psychology, distributive justice is defined as perceived fairness of how rewards and costs are shared by (distributed across) group members.[1] For example, when some workers work more hours but receive the same pay, group members may feel that distributive justice has not occurred. To determine whether distributive justice has taken place, individuals often turn to the behavioral expectations of their group.[1] If rewards and costs are allocated according to the designated distributive norms of the group, distributive justice has occurred.[2]

Distributive justice is also fundamental to the Catholic Church's social teaching, inspiring such figures as Dorothy Day[3] and Pope John Paul II.[4]

Types of distributive norms

Five types of distributive norm are defined by Donelson R. Forsyth:[1]

  1. Equality: Regardless of their inputs, all group members should be given an equal share of the rewards/costs. Equality supports that someone who contributes 20% of the group's resources should receive as much as someone who contributes 60%.
  2. Equity: Members' outcomes should be based upon their inputs. Therefore, an individual who has invested a large amount of input (e.g. time, money, energy) should receive more from the group than someone who has contributed very little. Members of large groups prefer to base allocations of rewards and costs on equity
  3. Power: Those with more authority, status, or control over the group should receive less than those in lower level positions.
  4. Need: Those in greatest needs should be provided with resources needed to meet those needs. These individuals should be given more resources than those who already possess them, regardless of their input.
  5. Responsibility: Group members who have the most should share their resources with those who have less.

Theories of distributive justice

To create a list of the theories of distributive justice will inevitably come with its implications. It is important to take into consideration the various nuances within each theory, as well as the development and variations in interpretations that exist for the theories presented in this article. The listed theories below are three of the most prominent Anglo-American theories within the field.[5] With this in mind, the list is in no way to be considered exhaustive for distributive justice theory.

Justice as fairness

In his book A Theory of Justice, John Rawls outlines his famous theory about justice as fairness. The theory consists of three core components:[6]

  1. the equality of people in rights and liberties;
  2. the equality of opportunities for all; and
  3. an arrangement of economic inequalities focused on benefit maximisation for those who are least advantaged.

The just 'basic structure'

Building a modern view on social contract theory, Rawls bases his work on an idea of justice being rooted in the basic structure, constituting the fundamental rules in society, which shape the social and economic institutions, as well as the governance.[7] This basic structure is what shapes the citizens’ life opportunities. According to Rawls, the structure is based on principles about basic rights and duties that any self-interested, rational individual would accept in order to further his/her own interests in a context of social cooperation.[7]

The original position

Rawls presents the concept of an original position as a hypothetical idea of how to establish "a fair procedure so that any principles agreed on will be just."[8] In his envisioning of the original position, it is created from a judgement made through negotiations between a group of men who will decide on what a just distribution of primary goods is (according to Rawls, the primary goods include freedoms, opportunities, and control over resources).[9] These men are assumed to be guided by self-interest, while also having a basic idea of morality and justice, and thus capable of understanding and evaluating a moral argument.[9] Rawls then argues that procedural justice in the process of negotiation will be possible via a nullification of temptations for these men to exploit circumstances so as to favor their own position in society.[8]

Veil of ignorance

This nullification of temptations is realised through a veil of ignorance, which these men will be behind. The veil prevents the men from knowing what particular preferences they will have by concealing their talents, objectives, and, most importantly, where in society they themselves will end up. The veil, on the other hand, does not conceal general information about the society, and the men are assumed to possess societal and economic knowledge beyond the personal level.[10] Thereby, such veil creates an environment for negotiations where the evaluation of the distribution of goods is based on general considerations, regardless of place in society, rather than biased considerations based on personal gains for specific citizen positions.[8] By this logic, the negotiations will be sensitive to both those who are worst off, given that a risk of being in that category yourself will incentivize protection of these people, but also the rest of society, as one would not wish to hinder maximal utilisation for these in case you would end up in higher classes.

Basic principles of a just distribution

In this original position, the main concern will be to secure the goods that are most essential for pursuing the goals of each individual, regardless of what this specific goal might be.[11] With this in mind, Rawls theorizes two basic principles of just distribution.

The first principle, the liberty principle, is the equal access to basic rights and liberties for all. With this, each person should be able to access the most extensive set of liberties that is compatible with similar schemes of access by other citizens. Thereby, it is not only a question of positive individual access but also of negative restrictions so as to respect others’ basic rights and liberties.[6]

The second principle, the difference principle, addresses how the arrangement of social and economic inequalities, and thus the just distribution should look. Firstly, Rawls argues that such distribution should be based on a reasonable expectation of advantage for all, but also to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged in society. Secondly, the offices and positions attached to this arrangement should be open to all.[6]

These principles of justice are then prioritised according to two additional principles:[6]

  1. the principles of the priority of liberty, wherein basic liberties only can be restricted if this is done for the sake of protecting liberty either:
    1. by strengthening “the total system of liberties shared by all;” or
    2. if a less than equal liberty is acceptable to those who are subject to this same lesser liberty.
  2. inequality of opportunity, and the priority of efficiency & welfare, can only be acceptable if:
    1. it enhances “the opportunities of those with lesser opportunities” in society; and/or
    2. excessive saving either balances out or lessens the gravity of hardship for those who do not traditionally benefit.

Utilitarianism

In 1789, Jeremy Bentham published his book An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. Centred around individual utility and welfare, utilitarianism builds on the notion that any action which increases the overall welfare in society is good, and any action that decreases welfare is bad. By this notion, utilitarianism's focus lies with its outcomes and pay little attention to how these outcomes are shaped.[12] This idea of utilisation maximisation, while being a much broader philosophical consideration, also translates into a theory of justice.[13]

Conceptualising welfare

While the basic notion that utilitarianism builds on seems simple, one major dispute within the school of utilitarianism revolved around the conceptualisation and measurement of welfare.[12] With disputes over this fundamental aspect, utilitarianism is evidently a broad term embracing many different sub-theories under its umbrella, and while much of the theoretical framework transects across these conceptualisations, using the different conceptualisation have clear implications for how we understand the more practical side of utilitarianism in distributive justice.

Bentham originally conceptualised this according to the hedonistic calculus, which also became the foundation for John Stuart Mill's focus on intellectual pleasures as the most beneficial contribution to societal welfare.[12] Another path has been painted by Aristotle, based on an attempt to create a more universal list of conditions required for human prosperity.[14] Opposite this, another path focuses on a subjective evaluation of happiness and satisfaction in human lives.[15]

Egalitarianism

Based on a fundamental notion of equal worth and moral status of human beings,[16] egalitarianism is concerned with equal treatment of all citizens in both respect and in concern, and in relation to the state as well as one another.[17] Egalitarianism focuses more on the process through which distribution takes place, egalitarianism evaluates the justification for a certain distribution based on how the society and its institutions have been shaped, rather than what the outcome is.[15] Attention is mainly given to ways in which unchosen person circumstances affect and hinder individuals and their life opportunities.[17] As Elizabeth Anderson defines it, "the positive aim of egalitarian justice is...to create a community in which people stand in relation of equality to others."[18]

While much academic work distinguishes between luck egalitarianism and social egalitarianism, Roland Pierik presents a synthesis combining the two branches.[17] In his synthesis, he argues that instead of focusing on compensations for unjust inequalities in society via redistribution of primary goods, egalitarianism scholars should instead, given the fundamental notion upon which the theory is built, strive to create institutions that creates and promotes meaningful equal opportunities from the get-go. Pierik thus moves egalitarianism's otherwise reactive nature by emphasising a need for attention to the development of fundamentally different institutions that would eradicate the need for redistribution and instead focus on the initial equal distribution of opportunities from which people then themselves be able to shape their lives.[17]

Application and outcomes

Outcomes

Distributive justice affects performance when efficiency and productivity are involved.[19] Improving perceptions of justice increases performance.[20] Organizational citizenship behaviors (OCBs) are employee actions in support of the organization that are outside the scope of their job description. Such behaviors depend on the degree to which an organization is perceived to be distributively just.[19][20] As organizational actions and decisions are perceived as more just, employees are more likely to engage in OCBs. Perceptions of distributive justice are also strongly related to the withdrawal of employees from the organization.[19]

Wealth

Distributive justice considers whether the distribution of goods among the members of society at a given time is subjectively acceptable.

Not all advocates of consequentialist theories are concerned with an equitable society. What unites them is the mutual interest in achieving the best possible results or, in terms of the example above, the best possible distribution of wealth.

Environmental justice

Distributive justice in an environmental context is the equitable distribution of a society's technological and environmental risks, impacts, and benefits. These burdens include air pollution, landfills, industrial factories, and other environmental burdens. Distributive justice is an essential principle of environmental justice because there is evidence that shows that these burdens cause health problems, negatively affect quality of life, and drive down property value.

The potential negative social impacts of environmental degradation and regulatory policies have been at the center environmental discussions since the rise of environmental justice.[21] Historically, in the United States, environmental burdens fall on poor communities that are predominantly African American, Native American, Latino, and Appalachian.[22]

In policy positions

Distributive justice theory argues that societies have a duty to individuals in need and that all individuals have a duty to help others in need. Proponents of distributive justice link it to human rights. Many governments are known for dealing with issues of distributive justice, especially countries with ethnic tensions and geographically distinctive minorities. Post-apartheid South Africa is an example of a country that deals with issues of re-allocating resources with respect to the distributive justice framework.

See also

Notes

  1. Forsyth, Donelson R. 2006. "Conflict." Pp. 388–89 in Group Dynamics (5th ed.), by D. R. Forsyth. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Cengage Learning.
  2. Deutsch, M. 1975. "Equity, equality, and need: What determines which value will be used as the basis of distributive justice?." Journal of Social Issues 31:137–49.
  3. Zwick, Mark and Louise (2005). The Catholic Worker Movement: Intellectual and Spiritual Origins. Paulist Press. ISBN 978-0809143153.
  4. "Catechism of the Catholic Church - Social justice". www.vatican.va. Retrieved 2018-11-03.
  5. Knight, Carl (20 Feb 2014). "Theories of Distributive Justice and Post-Apartheid South Africa" (PDF). Politikon. Volume 41, 2014 - Issue 1: 23–38. doi:10.1080/02589346.2014.885669. S2CID 154627483.
  6. Rawls, John (1999). A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition. Harvard University Press. pp. 266–67.
  7. Rawls, John (1999). A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition. Harvard University Press. pp. 10-15. ISBN 0-674-00078-1.
  8. Rawls, John (1999). A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition. Harvard University Press. p. 118.
  9. Rawls, John (1999). A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition. Harvard University Press. pp. 54-55.
  10. Rawls, John (1999). A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition. Harvard University Press. pp. 118-119.
  11. Rawls, John (1999). A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition. Harvard University Press. pp. 10-12.
  12. Knight, Carl (20 Feb 2014). "Theories of Distributive Justice and Post-Apartheid South Africa". Politikon. Volume 41, 2014 - Issue 1: 3–4 via Taylor & Francis Online.
  13. Mill, John Stuart (1969). Utilitarianism. Toronto University Press. pp. 241–242.
  14. Knoll, Manuel (2015). The Meaning of Distributive Justice for Aristotle's Theory of Constitutions. http://dx.doi.org/10.20318/fons.201. p. 66.CS1 maint: location (link)
  15. Sumner 1996 as referred to in, Carl Knight (20 Feb 2014). "Theories of distributive justice and post-apartheid South Africa" (PDF). Politikon. 41 (1): 23–38. doi:10.1080/02589346.2014.885669. S2CID 154627483.
  16. "Egalitarianism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. April 24, 2013. Retrieved May 15, 2020.
  17. Pierik, Roland. 2020. Developing responsibility-sensitive egalitarianism: A synthesis of five decades of liberal-egalitarian theorizing. University of Amsterdam. p. 16-17.
  18. Anderson, Elizanbeth (1999). What is the Point of Equality?. Chicago Journals: Chicago University Press. pp. 288–289.
  19. Cohen-Charash, Y., and P. E. Spector. 2001. "The role of justice in organizations: A meta-analysis." Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 86:278–321.
  20. Karriker, J. H., and M. L. Williams. 2009. "Organizational Justice and Organizational Citizenship Behavior: A Mediated Multifoci Model." Journal of Management 35:112.
  21. McGurty, Eileen (1997). "From NIMBY to Civil Rights: The Origins of the Environmental Justice Movement". Environmental History. 2 (3): 301–23. doi:10.2307/3985352. JSTOR 3985352.
  22. Shrader-Frenchette, Kristin (January 2006). Environmental Justice: Creating Equity, Reclaiming Democracy. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. p. 24. ISBN 9780198034704.

References

Further reading

  • Bullemore, Thomas (2013), Justicia Distributiva y Riesgos, Academia.edu
  • Hegtvedt, Karen A.; Markovsky, Barry (1995), "Justice and Injustice", in Cook, Karen S.; Fine, Gary Alan; House, James S. (eds.), Sociological Perspectives on Social Psychology (1 ed.), Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon (published 1994), pp. 257–280, ISBN 0-205-13716-4
  • Leventhal, Gerald S.; Karuza, Jurgis Jr.; Fry, William R. (1980), "Beyond Fairness: A Theory of Allocation Preferences", in Mikula, Gerald (ed.), Justice and Social Interaction: Experimental and Theoretical Contributions from Psychological Research, New York City, NY: Plenum, pp. 167–218, ISBN 3-456-80787-2
This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.