Hard problem of consciousness
The hard problem of consciousness is the problem of explaining why and how we have qualia[note 1] or phenomenal experiences. That is to say, it is the problem of why we have personal, first-person experiences, often described as experiences that feel "like something." In comparison, we assume there are no such experiences for inanimate things like, for instance, a thermostat, toaster, computer, or a sophisticated form of artificial intelligence.[2] The philosopher David Chalmers, who introduced the term "hard problem of consciousness,"[3] contrasts this with the "easy problems" of explaining the physical systems that give us and other animals the ability to discriminate, integrate information, report mental states, focus attention, and so forth.[4] Easy problems are (relatively) easy because all that is required for their solution is to specify a mechanism that can perform the function.[4] That is, even though we have yet to solve most of the easy problems (our understanding of the brain is still preliminary), these questions can probably eventually be understood by relying entirely on standard scientific methods.[4] Chalmers claims that even once we have solved such problems about the brain and experience, the hard problem will "persist even when the performance of all the relevant functions is explained".[4]
The existence of a "hard problem" is controversial. It has been accepted by philosophers of mind such as Joseph Levine,[5] Colin McGinn,[6] and Ned Block[7] and cognitive neuroscientists such as Francisco Varela,[8] Giulio Tononi,[9][10] and Christof Koch.[9][10] However, its existence is disputed by philosophers of mind such as Daniel Dennett,[11] Massimo Pigliucci,[12] Thomas Metzinger, Patricia Churchland,[13] and Keith Frankish,[14] and cognitive neuroscientists such as Stanislas Dehaene,[15] Bernard Baars,[16] Anil Seth[17] and Antonio Damasio.[18]
Overview
The hard problem is, to use the words of Annaka Harris, the question of "how experience arise[s] out of non-sentient matter".[19] David Chalmers first formulated the problem in his paper Facing up to the problem of consciousness (1995)[4] and expanded upon it in his book The Conscious Mind (1996). His works have proven to be provocative and have garnered a polarised response. Some, such as David Lewis and Steven Pinker, have praised Chalmers for his argumentative rigour and "impeccable clarity."[20] Others, such as Daniel Dennett and Patricia Churchland, believe that hard problem is really more of a collection of easy problems, and will be solved through further analysis of the brain and behaviour.[21][22]
Consciousness is an ambiguous term. It can be used to mean self consciousness, awareness, the state of being awake, and so on. Chalmers uses Thomas Nagel's definition of consciousness: the feeling of what it is like to be something. Consciousness, in this sense, is synonymous with experience.[23][20]
Chalmers' formulation
. . .even when we have explained the performance of all the cognitive and behavioral functions in the vicinity of experience—perceptual discrimination, categorization, internal access, verbal report—there may still remain a further unanswered question: Why is the performance of these functions accompanied by experience?
— David Chalmers, Facing up to the hard problem of consciousness
The problem of consciousness, Chalmers argues, is really two problems: the easy problems and the hard problem. The easy problems may include how sensory systems work, how such data is processed in the brain, how that data influences behaviour or verbal reports, the neural basis of thought and emotion, and so on. The hard problem is the problem of why and how are those processes accompanied by experience?[4] What's more, why are these processes accompanied by that particular experience rather than another experience?[20]
Easy problems
Chalmers use of the word easy is "tongue-in-cheek."[24] As Steven Pinker puts it, they are about as easy as going to Mars or curing cancer. "That is, scientists more or less know what to look for, and with enough brainpower and funding, they would probably crack it in this century."[25] The easy problems are amenable to reductive inquiry. They are a logical consequence of lower level facts about the world, similar to how a clock's ability to tell time is a logical consequence of its clockwork and structure, or a hurricane is a logical consequence of the structures and functions of certain weather patterns. A clock, a hurricane, and the easy problems, are all the sum of their parts (as are most things).[20]
The hard problem
Chalmers argues that experience is more than the sum of its parts. In other words, experience is irreducible. Unlike a clock, a hurricane, or the easy problems, descriptions of structures and functions leave something out of the picture. These functions and structures could conceivably exist in the absence of experience. Alternatively, they could exist alongside a different set of experiences. It is logically possible (though naturally impossible) for a perfect replica of Chalmers to have no experience at all. Alternatively, it is logically possible for the replica to have a different set of experiences, such as an inverted visible spectrum. The same cannot be said about clocks, hurricanes, or the easy problems. A perfect replica of a clock is a clock, a perfect replica of a hurricane is a hurricane, and a perfect replica of a behaviour is that behaviour. The difference, Chalmers argues, is that experience is not logically entailed by lower order structures and functions; it is not the sum of its physical parts. This means that experience is impervious to reductive analysis, and therefore poses a hard problem.[20]
Alternative formulations
Other formulations of the hard problem of consciousness include:
- "How is it that some organisms are subjects of experience?"
- "Why does awareness of sensory information exist at all?"
- "Why do qualia exist?"
- "Why is there a subjective component to experience?"
- "Why aren't we philosophical zombies?"
The philosopher Raamy Majeed argued in 2016 that the hard problem is, in fact, associated with two "explanatory targets":[26]
- [PQ] Physical processing gives rise to experiences with a phenomenal character.
- [Q] Our phenomenal qualities are thus-and-so.
The first fact concerns the relationship between the physical and the phenomenal (i.e., how and why are some physical states felt states), whereas the second concerns the very nature of the phenomenal itself (i.e., what does the felt state feel like?).
Wolfgang Fasching argues that the hard problem is not about qualia, but about pure what-it-is-like-ness of experience in Nagel's sense, about the very givenness of any phenomenal contents itself:
Today there is a strong tendency to simply equate consciousness with the qualia. Yet there is clearly something not quite right about this. The “itchiness of itches” and the “hurtfulness of pain” are qualities we are conscious of. So philosophy of mind tends to treat consciousness as if it consisted simply of the contents of consciousness (the phenomenal qualities), while it really is precisely consciousness of contents, the very givenness of whatever is subjectively given. And therefore the problem of consciousness does not pertain so much to some alleged “mysterious, nonpublic objects”, i.e. objects that seem to be only “visible” to the respective subject, but rather to the nature of “seeing” itself (and in today’s philosophy of mind astonishingly little is said about the latter).[27]
Historical predecessors
Wikiquote has quotations related to: Hard problem of consciousness |
The hard problem of consciousness has scholarly antecedents considerably earlier than Chalmers, as Chalmers himself has pointed out.[28][note 2] Among others, thinkers who have made arguments similar to Chalmers' formulation of the hard problem include Isaac Newton,[29] John Locke,[30] Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz,[31][32] John Stuart Mill, and Thomas Henry Huxley.[33]
What is it Like to be a Bat?
The philosopher Thomas Nagel posited in his 1974 paper "What is it like to be a bat?" that experiences are essentially subjective (accessible only to the individual undergoing them—i.e., felt only by the one feeling them), while physical states are essentially objective (accessible to multiple individuals). So at this stage, he argued, we have no idea what it could even mean to claim that an essentially subjective state just is an essentially non-subjective state (i.e., how and why a felt state is just a functional state). In other words, we have no idea of what reductivism really amounts to.[23] To explain conscious experience within the physicalist framework requires an adequate account. He believes this is impossible, because "every subjective phenomenon is essentially connected with a single point of view, and it seems inevitable that an objective, physical theory will abandon that point of view."[23]
The explanatory gap
In 1983, the philosopher Joseph Levine proposed that there is an explanatory gap between our understanding of the physical world and our understanding of consciousness.[34] He contended that a full explanation of a phenomenon should deductively entail it; that is, the conclusion (the phenomenon) must follow necessarily from the premises (the specifications of the explanation).[35] By contrast, he said, no matter how complete a physical explanation was, it would not entail subjective consciousness.[35]
Philosophical zombies
Philosophical zombies are a thought experiment commonly used in discussions of the hard problem.[36][37] They are hypothetical beings physically identical to humans but lack conscious experience.[38] Philosophers such as Chalmers, and Joseph Levine, and Francis Kripke take zombies as impossible within the bounds of nature but possible within the bounds of logic.[39] This would imply that facts about experience are not logically entailed by the "physical" facts. Therefore, consciousness is irreducible. In Chalmers words, "after God (hypothetically) created the world, he had more work to do."[40] Daniel Dennett, a philosopher of mind, has criticised the fields use of "the zombie hunch" which he deems an "embarrassment"[41] that ought to "be dropped like a hot potato."[21]
The knowledge argument
The Knowledge Argument, also known as Mary's Room, is another common thought experiment. It centres around a hypothetical neuroscientist named Mary. She has lived her whole life in a black and white room and has never seen colour before. She also happens to know everything there is to know about the brain and colour perception.[42] Chalmers believes that if Mary were to see the colour red for the first time that she would gain new knowledge of the world. That means knowledge of the what red looks like is distinct from knowledge of the brain or visual system. In other words knowledge of what red looks like is irreducible to knowledge of the brain or nervous system; therefore, experience is irreducible to the functioning of the brain or nervous system.[40] Others disagree, saying the same could be said about Mary knowing everything there is to know about bikes and riding one for the first time, or swimming, etc.[43] Elsewhere, Thomas Nagel has put forward a "speculative proposal" of devising a language that could "explain to a person blind from birth what it is like to see."[44] If such a language is possible then the force of the knowledge argument may be undercut.
Relationship to scientific frameworks
Most neuroscientists and cognitive scientists believe that Chalmers' alleged hard problem will be solved in the course of solving what he terms the easy problems, although a significant minority disagrees.[45][46]
Neural correlates of consciousness
Since 1990, researchers including the molecular biologist Francis Crick and the neuroscientist Christof Koch have made significant progress toward identifying which neurobiological events occur concurrently to the experience of subjective consciousness.[47] These postulated events are referred to as neural correlates of consciousness or NCCs. However, this research arguably addresses the question of which neurobiological mechanisms are linked to consciousness but not the question of why they should give rise to consciousness at all, the latter being the hard problem of consciousness as Chalmers formulated it. In "On the Search for the Neural Correlate of Consciousness", Chalmers said he is confident that, granting the principle that something such as what he terms global availability can be used as an indicator of consciousness, the neural correlates will be discovered "in a century or two".[48] Nevertheless, he stated regarding their relationship to the hard problem of consciousness:
One can always ask why these processes of availability should give rise to consciousness in the first place. As yet we cannot explain why they do so, and it may well be that full details about the processes of availability will still fail to answer this question. Certainly, nothing in the standard methodology I have outlined answers the question; that methodology assumes a relation between availability and consciousness, and therefore does nothing to explain it. [...] So the hard problem remains. But who knows: Somewhere along the line we may be led to the relevant insights that show why the link is there, and the hard problem may then be solved.[48]
The neuroscientist and Nobel laureate Eric Kandel wrote that locating the NCCs would not solve the hard problem, but rather one of the so-called easy problems to which the hard problem is contrasted.[49] Kandel went on to note Crick and Koch's suggestion that once the binding problem—understanding what accounts for the unity of experience—is solved, it will be possible to solve the hard problem empirically.[49] However, neuroscientist Anil Seth argued that emphasis on the so-called hard problem is a distraction from what he calls the "real problem": understanding the neurobiology underlying consciousness, namely the neural correlates of various conscious processes.[17] This more modest goal is the focus of most scientists working on consciousness.[49] Psychologist Susan Blackmore believes, by contrast, that the search for the neural correlates of consciousness is futile and itself predicated on an erroneous belief in the hard problem of consciousness.[50]
Integrated information theory
Integrated information theory (IIT), developed by the neuroscientist and psychiatrist Giulio Tononi in 2004 and more recently also advocated by Koch, is one of the most discussed models of consciousness in neuroscience and elsewhere.[51][52] The theory proposes an identity between consciousness and integrated information, with the latter item (denoted as Φ) defined mathematically and thus in principle measurable.[52][53] The hard problem of consciousness, write Tononi and Koch, may indeed be intractable when working from matter to consciousness.[10] However, because IIT inverts this relationship and works from phenomenological axioms to matter, they say it could be able to solve the hard problem.[10] In this vein, proponents have said the theory goes beyond identifying human neural correlates and can be extrapolated to all physical systems. Tononi wrote (along with two colleagues):
While identifying the “neural correlates of consciousness” is undoubtedly important, it is hard to see how it could ever lead to a satisfactory explanation of what consciousness is and how it comes about. As will be illustrated below, IIT offers a way to analyze systems of mechanisms to determine if they are properly structured to give rise to consciousness, how much of it, and of which kind.[54]
As part of a broader critique of IIT, Michael Cerullo suggested that the theory's proposed explanation is in fact for what he dubs (following Scott Aaronson) the "Pretty Hard Problem" of methodically inferring which physical systems are conscious—but would not solve Chalmers' hard problem.[52] "Even if IIT is correct," he argues, "it does not explain why integrated information generates (or is) consciousness."[52] Chalmers on the other hand has expressed some enthusiasm for IIT.[55]
Global workspace theory
Global workspace theory (GWT) is a cognitive architecture and theory of consciousness proposed by the cognitive psychologist Bernard Baars in 1988.[56] Baars explains the theory with the metaphor of a theater, with conscious processes represented by an illuminated stage.[56] This theater integrates inputs from a variety of unconscious and otherwise autonomous networks in the brain and then broadcasts them to unconscious networks (represented in the metaphor by a broad, unlit "audience").[56] The theory has since been expanded upon by other scientists including cognitive neuroscientist Stanislas Dehaene.[57]
In his original paper outlining the hard problem of consciousness, Chalmers discussed GWT as a theory that only targets one of the "easy problems" of consciousness.[4] In particular, he said GWT provided a promising account of how information in the brain could become globally accessible, but argued that "now the question arises in a different form: why should global accessibility give rise to conscious experience? As always, this bridging question is unanswered."[4] J. W. Dalton similarly criticized GWT on the grounds that it provides, at best, an account of the cognitive function of consciousness, and fails to explain its experiential aspect.[58] By contrast, A. C. Elitzur argued: "While [GWT] does not address the 'hard problem', namely, the very nature of consciousness, it constrains any theory that attempts to do so and provides important insights into the relation between consciousness and cognition."[59]
For his part, Baars writes (along with two colleagues) that there is no hard problem of explaining qualia over and above the problem of explaining causal functions, because qualia are entailed by neural activity and themselves causal.[16] Dehaene, in his 2014 book Consciousness and the Brain, rejected the concept of qualia and argued that Chalmers' "easy problems" of consciousness are actually the hard problems.[15] He further stated that the "hard problem" is based only upon ill-defined intuitions that are continually shifting as understanding evolves:[15]
Once our intuitions are educated by cognitive neuroscience and computer simulations, Chalmers' hard problem will evaporate. The hypothetical concept of qualia, pure mental experience, detached from any information-processing role, will be viewed as a peculiar idea of the prescientific era, much like vitalism... [Just as science dispatched vitalism] the science of consciousness will keep eating away at the hard problem of consciousness until it vanishes.
Responses
Chalmers' formulation of the hard problem of consciousness has provoked considerable debate within philosophy of mind as well as scientific research.[35] Some responses accept the problem as real and seek to develop a theory of consciousness' place in the world that can solve it, while others seek to show that the apparent hard problem as distinct from the easy problems dissolves upon analysis. A third response has been to accept the hard problem as real but deny human cognitive faculties can solve it.
Proposed solutions
Different solutions have been proposed to the hard problem of consciousness. One of these, weak reductionism, is the view that while there is an epistemic hard problem of consciousness that will not be solved directly by scientific progress, this is due to our conceptualization, not an ontological gap.[35] A traditional solution gaining renewed popularity is idealism, according to which consciousness is fundamental and not simply an emergent property of matter. It is claimed that this avoids the hard problem entirely.[60] Dualism views consciousness as either a non-physical substance separate from the brain or a non-physical property of the physical brain.[61] Meanwhile, panpsychism and neutral monism, broadly speaking, view consciousness as intrinsic to matter.[62]
Weak reductionism
There is a split among those subscribing to reductive materialism between those who hold there is no hard problem of consciousness—"strong reductionists" (see below)—and "weak reductionists" who, while remaining ontologically committed to physicalism, accept an epistemic hard problem of consciousness.[35][62] Put differently, weak reductionists believe there is a gap between two ways of knowing (introspection and neuroscience) that will not be resolved by understanding all the underlying neurobiology, but still believe that consciousness and neurobiology are one and the same in reality.[35] For example, Joseph Levine, who formulated the notion of the explanatory gap (see above), states: "The explanatory gap argument doesn't demonstrate a gap in nature, but a gap in our understanding of nature."[63] He nevertheless contends that a full scientific understanding will not close the gap,[35] and that analogous gaps do not exist for other identities in nature, such as that between water and H2O.[64] The philosophers Ned Block and Robert Stalnaker agree that facts about what a conscious experience is like to the one experiencing it cannot be deduced from knowing all the facts about the underlying physiology, but by contrast argue that such gaps of knowledge are also present in many other cases in nature, such as the distinction between water and H2O.[65][7]
To explain why these two ways of knowing (i.e. third-person scientific observation and first-person introspection) yield such different understandings of consciousness, weak reductionists often invoke the phenomenal concepts strategy, which argues the difference stems from our inaccurate phenomenal concepts (i.e., how we think about consciousness), not the nature of consciousness itself.[66][67] Thus, the hard problem of consciousness stems only from a dualism of concepts, not a dualism of properties or substances (see next section).[35]
Dualism
Dualism is the view that the mind is irreducible to the physical body.[61] There are multiple dualist accounts of the causal relationship between the mental and the physical, of which interactionism and epiphenomenalism are the most common today. Interactionism posits that the mental and physical causally impact one another, and is associated with the thought of René Descartes (1596–1650).[62] Epiphenomalism, by contrast, holds the mental is causally dependent on the physical, but does not in turn causally impact it.[62] In contemporary philosophy, interactionism has been defended by philosophers including Martine Nida-Rümelin,[68] while epiphenomenalism has been defended by philosophers including Frank Jackson[69][70] (although Jackson later changed his stance to physicalism).[71] Chalmers has also defended versions of both positions as plausible.[62] Traditional dualists such as Descartes believed the mental and the physical to be two separate substances, or fundamental types of entities (hence "substance dualism"); some more recent dualists (such as Chalmers[62]), however, accept only one substance, the physical, but state it has both mental and physical properties (hence "property dualism").[61]
Panpsychism and neutral monism
In its most basic form, panpsychism holds that all physical entities have minds (though its proponents in fact take more qualified positions),[72] while neutral monism, in at least some variations, holds that entities are composed of a substance with mental and physical aspects—and is thus sometimes described as a type of panpsychism.[73] Forms of panpsychism and neutral monism were defended in the early twentieth century by the psychologist William James,[74][75][note 3] the philosopher Alfred North Whitehead,[75] the physicist Arthur Eddington,[76][77] and the philosopher Bertrand Russell,[72][73] and interest in these views has been revived in recent decades by philosophers including Thomas Nagel,[75] Galen Strawson,[75][78] and David Chalmers.[72] Chalmers describes his overall view as "naturalistic dualism,"[4] but he says panpsychism is in a sense a form of physicalism,[62] as does Strawson.[78] Proponents of panpsychism argue it solves the hard problem of consciousness parsimoniously by making consciousness a fundamental feature of reality.[35][76]
Rejection of the problem
Many philosophers have disputed that there is a hard problem of consciousness distinct from what Chalmers calls the easy problems of consciousness. Some, termed strong reductionists, hold that phenomenal consciousness (i.e., conscious experience) does exist but that it can be fully understood as reducible to the brain.[35] Others maintain that phenomenal consciousness can be eliminated from the scientific picture of the world, and hence are called eliminative materialists or eliminativists.[35]
Strong reductionism
Broadly, strong reductionists accept that conscious experience is real but argue it can be fully understood in functional terms as an emergent property of the material brain.[35] In contrast to weak reductionists (see above), strong reductionists reject ideas used to support the existence of a hard problem (that the same functional organization could exist without consciousness, or that a blind person who understood vision through a textbook would not know everything about sight) as simply mistaken intuitions.[35][62]
A notable family of strong reductionist accounts are the higher-order theories of consciousness.[79][35] In 2005, the philosopher Peter Carruthers wrote about "recognitional concepts of experience," that is, "a capacity to recognize [a] type of experience when it occurs in one's own mental life," and suggested that such a capacity could explain phenomenal consciousness without positing qualia.[80] On the higher-order view, since consciousness is a representation, and representation is fully functionally analyzable, there is no hard problem of consciousness.[35]
The philosophers Glenn Carruthers and Elizabeth Schier said in 2012 that the main arguments for the existence of a hard problem—philosophical zombies, Mary's room, and Nagel's bats—are only persuasive if one already assumes that "consciousness must be independent of the structure and function of mental states, i.e. that there is a hard problem." Hence, the arguments beg the question. The authors suggest that "instead of letting our conclusions on the thought experiments guide our theories of consciousness, we should let our theories of consciousness guide our conclusions from the thought experiments."[81]
The philosopher Massimo Pigliucci argued in 2013 that the hard problem is misguided, resulting from a "category mistake."[12] He said: "Of course an explanation isn't the same as an experience, but that's because the two are completely independent categories, like colors and triangles. It is obvious that I cannot experience what it is like to be you, but I can potentially have a complete explanation of how and why it is possible to be you."[12]
In 2017, the philosopher Marco Stango, in a paper on John Dewey's approach to the problem of consciousness (which preceded Chalmers' formulation of the hard problem by over half a century), noted that Dewey's approach would see the hard problem as the consequence of an unjustified assumption that feelings and functional behaviors are not the same physical process: "For the Deweyan philosopher, the 'hard problem' of consciousness is a 'conceptual fact' only in the sense that it is a philosophical mistake: the mistake of failing to see that the physical can be had as an episode of immediate sentiency."[82]
The philosopher Thomas Metzinger likens the hard problem of consciousness to vitalism, a formerly widespread view in biology which was not so much solved as much as abandoned.[83] Brian Jonathan Garrett has also argued that the hard problem suffers from flaws analogous to those of vitalism.[84]
Eliminative materialism
Eliminative materialism or eliminativism is the view that many or all of the mental states used in folk psychology (i.e., common-sense ways of discussing the mind) do not, upon scientific examination, correspond to real brain mechanisms.[85] While Patricia Churchland and Paul Churchland have famously applied eliminative materialism to propositional attitudes, philosophers including Daniel Dennett, Georges Rey, and Keith Frankish have applied it to qualia or phenomenal consciousness (i.e., conscious experience).[85] On their view, it is mistaken not only to believe there is a hard problem of consciousness, but to believe consciousness exists at all (in the sense of phenomenal consciousness).[14][86]
Dennett asserts that the so-called "hard problem" will be solved in the process of solving what Chalmers terms the "easy problems."[11] He compares consciousness to stage magic and its capability to create extraordinary illusions out of ordinary things.[87] To show how people might be commonly fooled into overstating the accuracy of their introspective abilities, he describes a phenomenon called change blindness, a visual process that involves failure to detect scenery changes in a series of alternating images.[88] He accordingly argues that consciousness need not be what it seems to be based on introspection. To address the question of the hard problem, or how and why physical processes give rise to experience, Dennett states that the phenomenon of having experience is nothing more than the performance of functions or the production of behavior, which can also be referred to as the easy problems of consciousness.[11] Thus, Dennett argues that the hard problem of experience is included among—not separate from—the easy problems, and therefore they can only be explained together as a cohesive unit.[87]
In 2013, the philosopher Elizabeth Irvine argued that both science and folk psychology do not treat mental states as having phenomenal properties, and therefore "the hard problem of consciousness may not be a genuine problem for non-philosophers (despite its overwhelming obviousness to philosophers), and questions about consciousness may well 'shatter' into more specific questions about particular capacities."[89]
In 2016, Frankish proposed the term "illusionism" as superior to "eliminativism" for describing the position that phenomenal consciousness is an illusion. In the introduction to his paper, he states: "Theories of consciousness typically address the hard problem. They accept that phenomenal consciousness is real and aim to explain how it comes to exist. There is, however, another approach, which holds that phenomenal consciousness is an illusion and aims to explain why it seems to exist."[14] After offering arguments in favor and responding to objections, Frankish concludes that illusionism "replaces the hard problem with the illusion problem — the problem of explaining how the illusion of phenomenality arises and why it is so powerful."[14]
A complete illusionist theory of consciousness must include the description of a mechanism by which the apparently subjective aspect of consciousness is perceived and reported by people. Various philosophers and scientists have proposed possible theories.[90] For example, in his book Consciousness and the Social Brain neuroscientist Michael Graziano advocates what he calls attention schema theory, in which our perception of being conscious is merely an error in perception, held by brains which evolved to hold erroneous and incomplete models of their own internal workings, just as they hold erroneous and incomplete models of their own bodies and of the external world.[91][92]
Other views
The philosopher Peter Hacker argues that the hard problem is misguided in that it asks how consciousness can emerge from matter, whereas in fact sentience emerges from the evolution of living organisms.[93] He states: "The hard problem isn’t a hard problem at all. The really hard problems are the problems the scientists are dealing with. [...] The philosophical problem, like all philosophical problems, is a confusion in the conceptual scheme."[93] Hacker's critique extends beyond Chalmers and the hard problem and is directed against contemporary philosophy of mind and neuroscience more broadly. Along with the neuroscientist Max Bennett, he has argued that most of contemporary neuroscience remains implicitly dualistic in its conceptualizations and is predicated on the mereological fallacy of ascribing psychological concepts to the brain that can properly be ascribed only to the person as a whole.[94] Hacker further states that "consciousness studies," as it exists today, is "literally a total waste of time":[93]
The whole endeavour of the consciousness studies community is absurd—they are in pursuit of a chimera. They misunderstand the nature of consciousness. The conception of consciousness which they have is incoherent. The questions they are asking don't make sense. They have to go back to the drawing board and start all over again.
New mysterianism
New mysterianism, most significantly associated with the philosopher Colin McGinn, proposes that the human mind, in its current form, will not be able to explain consciousness.[95][6] McGinn draws on Noam Chomsky's distinction between problems, which are in principle solvable, and mysteries, which human cognitive faculties are unequipped to ever understand, and places the mind-body problem in the latter category.[95] His position is that a naturalistic explanation does exist but that the human mind is cognitively closed to it due to its limited range of intellectual abilities.[95] He cites Jerry Fodor's concept of the modularity of mind in support of cognitive closure.[95]
While in McGinn's strong form, new mysterianism states that the relationship between consciousness and the material world can never be understood by the human mind, there are also weaker forms that argue it cannot be understood within existing paradigms but that advances in science or philosophy may open the way to other solutions (see above).[35] The ideas of Thomas Nagel and Joseph Levine fall into the second category.[35] The cognitive psychologist Steven Pinker has also endorsed this weaker version of the view, summarizing it as follows:[45]
And then there is the theory put forward by philosopher Colin McGinn that our vertigo when pondering the Hard Problem is itself a quirk of our brains. The brain is a product of evolution, and just as animal brains have their limitations, we have ours. Our brains can't hold a hundred numbers in memory, can't visualize seven-dimensional space and perhaps can't intuitively grasp why neural information processing observed from the outside should give rise to subjective experience on the inside. This is where I place my bet, though I admit that the theory could be demolished when an unborn genius—a Darwin or Einstein of consciousness—comes up with a flabbergasting new idea that suddenly makes it all clear to us.
The meta-problem
In 2018, Chalmers highlighted what he calls the "meta-problem of consciousness", another problem related to the hard problem of consciousness:[90]
The meta-problem of consciousness is (to a first approximation) the problem of explaining why we think that there is a [hard] problem of consciousness.
In his "second approximation", he says it is the problem of explaining the behavior of "phenomenal reports", and the behavior of expressing a belief that there is a hard problem of consciousness.[90]
Explaining its significance, he says:[90]
Although the meta-problem is strictly speaking an easy problem, it is deeply connected to the hard problem. We can reasonably hope that a solution to the meta-problem will shed significant light on the hard problem. A particularly strong line holds that a solution to the meta-problem will solve or dissolve the hard problem. A weaker line holds that it will not remove the hard problem, but it will constrain the form of a solution.
In popular culture
British playwright Sir Tom Stoppard's play The Hard Problem, first produced in 2015, is named after the hard problem of consciousness, which Stoppard defines as having "subjective First Person experiences."[96]
See also
Notes
- The term qualia is used in at least two different senses by different authors. Keith Frankish (2012) distinguishes between "classic qualia," which are "introspectable qualitative properties of experience that are intrinsic, ineffable, and subjective" (close to the original definition of C. I. Lewis), and "diet qualia," which are conceptualized more modestly as "what it is like" to have subjective experience (close to the definition of, for example, Ned Block).[1] The latter is synonymous with phenomenal experiences.[1]
- Chalmers (1997) states: "Any number of thinkers in the recent and distant past – including a number of contributors to this symposium – have recognized the particular difficulties of explaining consciousness and have tried to face up to them in various ways. All my paper really contributes is a catchy name, a minor reformulation of philosophically familiar points, and a specific approach to dealing with them."
- There has been debate over how best to characterize James' position. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy states: "James’s commitment to panpsychism remains somewhat controversial, since he also advanced a cogent set of objections against a version of the view, which he labelled the 'mind dust' theory, in chapter six of The Principles of Psychology ([1890] 1981). These objections are the inspiration for the so-called 'combination problem', around which much of the twenty first century literature on panpsychism focuses. But in the end James’s commitment is quite clear (see James 1909, 1911; Lamberth 1997; and for an excellent analysis of James’s views on mind see Cooper 1990 or chapters 2–4 of Cooper 2002)."
References
- Frankish, Keith (2012). "Quining diet qualia" (PDF). Consciousness and Cognition. 21 (2): 667–76. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2011.04.001. PMID 21543237. S2CID 33488265. Retrieved 5 November 2019.
- Harnad, Stevan (1995). "Why and how we are not zombies". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 1: 164–167. See also Harnad, Stevan (April 2000). "How/why the mind-body problem is hard". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 7 (4): 54–61.
- See Cooney's foreword to the reprint of Chalmers' paper: Brian Cooney, ed. (1999). "Chapter 27: Facing up to the problem of consciousness". The place of mind. Cengage Learning. pp. 382 ff. ISBN 978-0534528256.
- Chalmers, David (1995). "Facing up to the problem of consciousness" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 2 (3): 200–219.
- Levine, Joseph (2009-01-15). "The Explanatory Gap". The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0017.
- McGinn, Colin (20 February 2012). "All machine and no ghost?". New Statesman. Retrieved 27 March 2012.
- Block, Ned (2002). "The Harder Problem of Consciousness". The Journal of Philosophy. 99 (8): 391–425. doi:10.2307/3655621. JSTOR 3655621. S2CID 111383062.
- Varela, F. J. (1996-04-01). "Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy for the hard problem". www.ingentaconnect.com. Retrieved 2019-07-29.
- Koch, Christof; Marcello Massimini; Boly, Melanie; Tononi, Giulio (July 2016). "Integrated information theory: from consciousness to its physical substrate". Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 17 (7): 450–461. doi:10.1038/nrn.2016.44. ISSN 1471-0048. PMID 27225071. S2CID 21347087.
- Tononi, Giulio; Koch, Christof (March 2015). "Consciousness: here, there and everywhere?". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 370 (1668): 20140167. doi:10.1098/rstb.2014.0167. PMC 4387509. PMID 25823865.
- Dennett, Daniel C. (2013). "The tuned deck". Intuition pumps and other tools for thinking. W. W. Norton & Company. pp. 310 ff. ISBN 978-0393240689. and also "Commentary on Chalmers": Dennett, Daniel C. (1996). "Facing backwards on the problem of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 3 (1): 4–6.
- Massimo Pigliucci (2013). "What hard problem?" (PDF). Philosophy Now (99).
- Churchland, Patricia (1996). "The Hornswoggle Problem" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 3 (5–6): 402–408. Retrieved 10 January 2021.
- Frankish, Keith (2016). "Illusionism as a Theory of Consciousness" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 23 (11–12): 11–39. Retrieved 20 December 2018.
- Dehaene, Stanislas (2014). Consciousness and the brain: deciphering how the brain codes our thoughts. Viking Adult. pp. 259–266. ISBN 978-0670025435.
- Edelman, Gerald; Gally, Joseph; Baars, Bernard (2011). "Biology of Consciousness". Frontiers in Psychology. 2 (4): 4. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2011.00004. PMC 3111444. PMID 21713129.
- Seth, Anil (November 2016). "The real problem". Aeon. Retrieved 22 April 2018.
-
Sean Carroll (29 April 2019). "SEAN CARROLL'S MINDSCAPE". Preposterousuniverse.com (Podcast). Sean Carroll. Event occurs at 1:04.46.
I’m just saying that the idea of a hard problem that you cannot transpose, I think is wrong.
- Harris, Annaka (2020-02-27). "Consciousness Isn't Self-Centered". Nautilus. Retrieved 2020-09-05.
- Chalmers, David (1996). The Conscious Mind. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. xii–xiii, 95–106, backcover.
- Dennett, Daniel; commentary on T. Moody, O. Flanagan and T. Polger. "The Unimagined Preposterous of Zombies", Journal of Consciousness Studies vol. 2, no. 4, 1995, pp. 322–326.
- Churchland, Patrica (2005). "A neurophilosophical slant on consciousness research" (PDF). Progress in Brain Research. 149: Chapter 20. PMID 16226591.
- Nagel, Thomas (October 1974). "What is it like to be a bat?". The Philosophical Review. 83 (4): 435–450. doi:10.2307/2183914. JSTOR 2183914. S2CID 49125889.
- "Episode 83, The David Chalmers Interview (Part I - Consciousness)". The Panpsycast Philosophy Podcast. Retrieved 2020-09-05.
- Pinker, Steven (2007-01-29). "The Brain: The Mystery of Consciousness". Time. ISSN 0040-781X. Retrieved 2020-09-05.
- Majeed, Raamy (September 2016). "The hard problem & its explanatory targets". Ratio. 29 (3): 298–311. doi:10.1111/rati.12103.
- Fasching, W. Prakāśa. A few reflections on the Advaitic understanding of consciousness as presence and its relevance for philosophy of mind. Phenom Cogn Sci (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-020-09690-2
- Chalmers, David (January 1997). "Moving forward on the problem of consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies. 4 (1): 3–46.
- Seager, William; Allen-Hermanson, Sean (2010). "Panpsychism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- Locke, John (1722). The works of John Locke: in three volumes. 1. London: Printed for A. Churchill, and A. Manship, and sold by W. Taylor in Pater-noster-Row. p. 293.
- Lisman, John E. (2017-06-23). "Locke's View of the Hard Problem of Consciousness and Its Implications for Neuroscience and Computer Science". Frontiers in Psychology. 8: 1069. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01069. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 5481348. PMID 28690580.
- Leibniz, Monadology, 17, as quoted by Aranyosi, Istvan (2004). "Chalmers's zombie arguments" (PDF) (draft ed.). Central European University Personal Pages.
- Huxley, Thomas Henry; Youmans, William Jay (1868). The elements of physiology and hygiene: a text-book for educational institutions. New York: D. Appleton and company. p. 178.
- Levine, J. 1983. “Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap”. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64: 354-361.
- Weisberg, Josh. "The Hard Problem of Consciousness". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISSN 2161-0002. Retrieved 11 September 2018.
- Seager, William. "Are Zombies Logically Possible?". www.utsc.utoronto.ca. Retrieved 2020-09-03.
- Kaszniak, Alfred W.; Scott, Andrew C. (2007). "Zombie Killer". www.semanticscholar.org. S2CID 14891432. Retrieved 2020-09-03.
- Polger, Tom. "Zombies: Entry". host.uniroma3.it. Retrieved 2020-09-03.
- Kirk, Robert (2019), "Zombies", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2020-09-03
- David Chalmers (1996) The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory, pp. 153–6. Oxford University Press, New York, ISBN 0-19-511789-1 (Pbk.)
- Dennett, Daniel (1999), "The Zombie Hunch: Extinction of an Intuition?", Royal Institute of Philosophy Millennial Lecture
- Nida-Rümelin, Martine; O Conaill, Donnchadh (2019), "Qualia: The Knowledge Argument", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2020-09-03
- Nida-Rümelin, Martine; O Conaill, Donnchadh (2019), "Qualia: The Knowledge Argument", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2020-09-03
- Nagel, Thomas. "What is it Like to be a Bat?". From The Philosophical Review LXXXIII, 4 (October 1974), pp. 435–450
- Pinker, Steven (2007-01-29). "The Brain: The Mystery of Consciousness". Time. Retrieved 19 December 2018.
- Dennett, Daniel (2014). "The Hard Problem". Edge.org. Retrieved 11 April 2019.
- Koch, Christof; Massimini, Marcello; Boly, Melanie; Tononi, Giulio (April 2016). "Neural correlates of consciousness: Progress and problems". Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 17 (5): 307–321. doi:10.1038/nrn.2016.22. PMID 27094080. S2CID 5395332. Retrieved 14 April 2018.
- Chalmers, David (1998). "On the Search for the Neural Correlate of Consciousness" (PDF). In Hameroff, Stuart; Kaszniak, Alfred; Scott, Alwyn (eds.). Toward a Science of Consciousness II. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ISBN 9780262082624. Retrieved 17 April 2018.
- Kandel Eric R. (2007). In search of memory: The emergence of a new science of mind. W. W. Norton & Company. pp. 380–382. ISBN 978-0393329377.
- Blackmore, Susan (2014). "The Neural Correlates of Consciousness". Edge.org. Retrieved 22 April 2018.
- Krohn, Stephan; Ostwald, Dirk (2017). "Computing integrated information". Neuroscience of Consciousness. 2017 (1): nix017. doi:10.1093/nc/nix017. PMC 6007153. PMID 30042849.
- Cerullo, Michael A. (September 2015). Kording, Konrad P. (ed.). "The Problem with Phi: A Critique of Integrated Information Theory". PLOS Computational Biology. 11 (9): e1004286. Bibcode:2015PLSCB..11E4286C. doi:10.1371/journal.pcbi.1004286. PMC 4574706. PMID 26378789.
- Mørch, Hedda Hassel (2017). "The Integrated Information Theory of Consciousness". Philosophy Now. Retrieved 22 April 2018.
- Oizumi, Masafumi; Albantakis, Larissa; Tononi, Giulio (May 2014). "From the Phenomenology to the Mechanisms of Consciousness: Integrated Information Theory 3.0". PLOS Computational Biology. 10 (5): e1003588. Bibcode:2014PLSCB..10E3588O. doi:10.1371/journal.pcbi.1003588. PMC 4014402. PMID 24811198.
- Chalmers, David, How do you explain consciousness?, retrieved 2019-03-11
- Baars, Bernard (2005). "Global workspace theory of consciousness: toward a cognitive neuroscience of human experience?". Progress in Brain Research. 150: 45–53. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.456.2829. doi:10.1016/S0079-6123(05)50004-9. ISBN 9780444518514. PMID 16186014.
- Dehaene, Stanislas; Naccache, Lionel (2001). "Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: basic evidence and a workspace framework" (PDF). Cognition. 79 (1–2): 1–37. doi:10.1016/S0010-0277(00)00123-2. PMID 11164022. S2CID 1762431. Retrieved 5 April 2019.
- Dalton, J. W. The unfinished theatre, JCS, 4 (4), 1997, pp. 316–18
- Elitzur, A. C. Why don't we know what Mary knows? Baars' reversing the problem of qualia. JCS, 4 (4), 1997, pp. 319–24
- https://philpapers.org/rec/KASTUI
- Calef, Scott (2014). "Dualism and Mind". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISSN 2161-0002. Retrieved 8 February 2019.
- Chalmers, David J. (2003). "Consciousness and its Place in Nature" (PDF). In Stich, Stephen P.; Warfield, Ted A. (eds.). The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind (1st ed.). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing Ltd. ISBN 978-0631217756. Archived from the original (PDF) on 3 October 2017. Retrieved 21 January 2018.
- J. Levine, "Conceivability, Identity, and the Explanatory Gap" in Stuart R. Hameroff, Alfred W. Kaszniak and David Chalmers (eds.), Towards a Science of Consciousness III: The Third Tucson Discussions and Debates, The MIT Press, 1999,. pp 3-12.
- Gennaro, Rocco J. "Consciousness". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISSN 2161-0002. Retrieved 9 March 2019.
- Block, Ned; Stalnaker, Robert (1999). "Conceptual Analysis, Dualism, and the Explanatory Gap" (PDF). The Philosophical Review. 108 (1): 1–46. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.693.2421. doi:10.2307/2998259. JSTOR 2998259.
- Stoljar, Daniel (2005). "Physicalism and Phenomenal Concepts". Mind & Language. 20 (5): 469–494.
- Chalmers, David (2006). "Phenomenal Concepts and the Explanatory Gap" (PDF). In Alter, Torin; Walter, Sven (eds.). Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780195171655. Retrieved 27 March 2019.
- Nida-Rümelin, Martine (2006). "Dualist Emergentism" (PDF). In McLaughlin, Brian; Cohen, Jonathan (eds.). Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind (1st ed.). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-405-11761-6. Retrieved 1 February 2019.
- Jackson, Frank (1982). "Epiphenomenal Qualia". The Philosophical Quarterly. 32 (127): 127–136. doi:10.2307/2960077. JSTOR 2960077.
- Jackson, Frank (1986). "What Mary Didn't Know". The Journal of Philosophy. 83 (5): 291–295. doi:10.2307/2026143. JSTOR 2026143. S2CID 19000667.
- Jackson, Frank (2003). "Mind and Illusion". Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements. 53: 251–271. doi:10.1017/S1358246100008365. Retrieved 6 February 2019.
- Chalmers, David (2015). "Panpsychism and Panprotopsychism" (PDF). In Alter, Torin; Nagasawa, Yugin (eds.). Consciousness in the Physical World: Perspectives on Russellian Monism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-992735-7. Retrieved 15 September 2018.
- Stubenberg, Leopold (2016). "Neutral monism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 15 September 2018.
- Koch, Christof. "Is Consciousness Universal?". Scientific American. doi:10.1038/scientificamericanmind0114-26. Retrieved 13 September 2018.
- Goff, Philip; Seager, William; Allen-Hermanson, Sean (2017). "Panpsychism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 15 September 2018.
- Goff, Philip (2017). "The Case for Panpsychism". Philosophy Now. Retrieved 3 October 2018.
- Skrbina, David. "Panpsychism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISSN 2161-0002. Retrieved 8 February 2019.
- Strawson, Galen (2006). "Realistic monism: Why physicalism entails panpsychism" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 13 (10/11): 3–31. Retrieved 15 September 2018.
- Carruthers, Peter (2016). "Higher-order theories of consciousness". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- Carruthers, Peter (2005). "Phenomenal concepts and higher-order experiments". Consciousness: essays from a higher-order perspective. Oxford University Press. pp. 79 ff. ISBN 978-0191535048.
- Carruthers, Glenn; Schier, Elizabeth (2012). "Dissolving the hard problem of consciousness" (PDF). Consciousness Online fourth conference. Retrieved 7 July 2014.
- Stango, Marco (Summer 2017). "A Deweyan assessment of three major tendencies in philosophy of consciousness". Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 53 (3): 466–490. doi:10.2979/trancharpeirsoc.53.3.06. S2CID 148690536.
- Harris, Sam. "Making Sense #96". SamHarris.org. Sam Harris. Retrieved 27 August 2020.
(25.45) TM:I think it will not be a mystery. Life is not a mystery anymore, but a hundred and fifty years ago many people thought that this is an irreducible mystery. (25:57) Harris:So you’re not a fan anymore, if you ever were, of the framing by David Chalmers of the Hard Problem of Consciousness? Metzinger: No, that’s so boring. I mean, that’s last century. I mean, you know, we all respect Dave [Chalmers], and we know he is very smart and has got a very fast mind, no debate about that. But conceivability arguments are just very, very weak. If you have an ill-defined folk psychological umbrella term like “consciousness”, then you can pull off all kinds of scenarios and zombie thought experiments. It doesn’t really… It helped to clarify some issues in the mid 90’s, but the consciousness community has listened to this and just moved on. I mean nobody of the serious researchers in the field thinks about this anymore, but it has taken on like a folkloristic life of its own. A lot of people talk about the Hard Problem who wouldn’t be able to state what it consists in now.
- Garrett, Brian Jonathan (2006). "What the History of Vitalism Teaches Us About Consciousness and the "Hard Problem"". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 72 (3): 576–588. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2006.tb00584.x. ISSN 1933-1592.
- Ramsey, William (2019). "Eliminative Materialism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 1 April 2019.
- Dennett, Daniel (2016). "Illusionism as the Obvious Default Theory of Consciousness" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 23 (11–12): 65–72. Retrieved 20 March 2019.
- Dennett, Daniel C. (2003). "Explaining the 'magic' of consciousness". Journal of Cultural and Evolutionary Psychology. 1 (1): 7–19. doi:10.1556/jcep.1.2003.1.2. S2CID 144560246.
- Dennett, Daniel C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Company. ISBN 978-0316180658.
- Irvine, Elizabeth (2013). Consciousness as a scientific concept: a philosophy of science perspective. Studies in brain and mind. 5. Dordrecht; New York: Springer-Verlag. p. 167. ISBN 9789400751729.
- Chalmers, David (2018). "The Meta-Problem of Consciousness" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 25 (9–10): 6–61. Retrieved 6 February 2019.
- Graziano, Michael (2013). Consciousness and the social brain. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0190263195.
- Michael Graziano (10 July 2015). "Build-a-brain". aeon.co. Retrieved 19 April 2018.
- Hacker, Peter (2010). "Hacker's challenge". The Philosophers' Magazine. 51 (51): 23–32. doi:10.5840/tpm2010517.
- Schaal, David W. (2005). "Naming Our Concerns About Neuroscience: A Review of Bennett and Hacker's Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience". Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior. 84 (3): 683–692. doi:10.1901/jeab.2005.83-05. PMC 1389787. PMID 16596986.
- McGinn, Colin (1989). "Can We Solve the Mind-Body Problem?". Mind. 98 (391): 349–366. doi:10.1093/mind/XCVIII.391.349. JSTOR 2254848.
- Stoppard, Tom (28 January 2015). "First Person". Programme notes. London: Royal National Theatre.
External links
- Weisberg, Josh. "The hard problem of consciousness". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.