Pre-Socratic philosophy
Pre-Socratic philosophy is ancient Greek philosophy before Socrates and schools contemporary to Socrates that were not influenced by him.[1] In Classical antiquity, these thinkers were sometimes called physiologoi (Greek: φυσιολόγοι; in English, physical or natural philosophers)[2] or sophoi (sages or wise men). Thales, one of the Seven Sages of Greece, is considered the first philosopher. The inquiries of these early philosophers spanned the workings of the natural world as well as human society, ethics, and religion, seeking explanations based on natural principles rather than the actions of gods. They introduced to the West the notion of the world as a kosmos, an ordered arrangement that could be understood via rational inquiry.[3] The pre-Socratics were the forerunners of what became Western philosophy as well as natural philosophy, which later developed into the natural sciences (such as physics, chemistry, geology, and astronomy).[3] Significant figures include: the Milesians, Xenophanes, Heraclitus, Parmenides, Empedocles, Zeno of Elea, Anaxagoras, Democritus, and Pythagoras.
History of Western philosophy |
---|
The School of Athens fresco by Raphael |
Western philosophy |
|
|
See also |
Overview
Pre-Socratic is a term formulated in the 19th century for this group of philosophers. In earlier literature they were referred to as physiologoi or physikoi ("physicists", after physis, "nature"), with this usage arising with Aristotle to differentiate them from theologoi (theologians) and mythologoi (storytellers and bards who conveyed Greek mythology) who attributed natural phenomena to the gods.[4] The term is problematic. It is chronologically inaccurate, as the last of the pre-Socratics were contemporaries of Socrates. While the term was intended to mark a contrast between Socrates, who was interested in moral problems, and his predecessors, who were viewed to be primarily concerned with cosmological and physical problems; this is inaccurate because several of the pre-Socratics were highly interested in ethics and how to live the best life. Further, the term implies that the pre-Socratics are somehow inferior to Socrates, and that philosophy only becomes interesting in the Classical period of Plato and Aristotle.[5]
Doxography
The knowledge we have of the pre-Socratics derives from accounts, known as doxography, of later philosophical writers (especially Aristotle, Plutarch, Diogenes Laërtius, Stobaeus, and Simplicius), and some early Christian theologians (especially Clement of Alexandria and Hippolytus of Rome). Only fragments of the original writings of the pre-Socratics survive. Many of these are titled Peri Physeos, or On Nature, a title probably attributed later by other authors).[6] The translation of Peri Physeos as On Nature may be misleading: the "on" normally gives the idea of an "erudite dissertation", while "peri" may refer in fact to a "circular approach"; and the traditional meanings of "nature" for us (as opposition to culture, to supernatural, or as essence, substance, opposed to accident, etc.) may be in contrast with the meaning of "physeos" or "physis" for the Greeks (referring to an "originary source", or "process of emergence and development").[7] As all that is available about the pre-Socratics are quotations and testimonies by (often biased) later philosophers and historians, it is sometimes difficult to determine the actual line of argument some pre-Socratics used in supporting their views.
History
Pre-Socratic philosophy arose from the Ionian Enlightenment, which was a set of advances in scientific thought, explanations on nature, and inquiring into the natural and rational causes behind observable phenomena, that took place in Ionia (archaic eastern Greece) beginning in the 6th century BC. According to C. Stephen Evans, Ionian towns, especially Miletus, had close trade relations with Egypt and Mesopotamia, cultures with observations about the natural world that differed from those of the Greeks, which prompted early Greek thinkers to view them as natural phenomena. Another factor was that these Greek towns were not ruled by autocrats or priests, allowing citizens to freely question a wide range of issues.[8]
Diogenes Laërtius divided the physiologoi into two groups: the Ionian, begun by Anaximander, and the Italiote, begun by Pythagoras.[9]
Modern interest in early Greek philosophy can be traced back to 1573, when Henri Estienne collected a number of pre-Socratic fragments in Poesis Philosophica (Ποίησις Φιλόσοφος).[10] Hermann Diels popularized the term "pre-Socratic" in Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (The Fragments of the Pre-Socratics) in 1903. The term "pre-Sokratic" [sic] was used as early as George Grote's Plato and the Other Companions of Sokrates in 1865. Edouard Zeller was also important in dividing thought before and after Socrates.[11] Major analyses of pre-Socratic thought have been made by Gregory Vlastos, Jonathan Barnes, Karl Popper,[12] and Friedrich Nietzsche.[13]
Focus and aims
The pre-Socratic philosophers rejected traditional mythological explanations of the phenomena they saw around them in favor of more rational explanations. Their efforts were directed to the investigation of the ultimate basis and essential nature of the external world.[14] Many sought the material principle (archê) of things, and the method of their origin and disappearance.[14] As the first philosophers, they emphasized the rational unity of things and rejected supernatural explanations, instead seeking natural principles at work in the world and human society. The pre-Socratics saw the world as a kosmos, an ordered arrangement that could be understood via rational inquiry.[3] Pre-Socratic thinkers present a discourse concerned with key areas of philosophical inquiry such as being, the primary stuff of the universe, the structure and function of the human soul, and the underlying principles governing perceptible phenomena, human knowledge, and morality.
These philosophers asked questions about "the essence of things":[15]
- From where does everything come?
- From what is everything created?
- How do we explain the plurality of things found in nature?
- How might we describe nature mathematically?
Others concentrated on defining problems and paradoxes that became the basis for later mathematical, scientific, and philosophic study.
The schools
Ionian school
The Ionian school was centred in Miletus, Ionia in the 6th century BC. Miletus and its environs was a thriving mercantile melting pot of current ideas of the time.[16] The School included philosophers such as Thales, Anaximander, Anaximenes, Heraclitus, Anaxagoras, and Archelaus.[17] Aristotle called them physiologoi (φυσιολόγοι),[18] meaning "those who discoursed on nature." While some of these scholars are included in the Milesian school of philosophy, others are more difficult to categorize.
Milesian school
The first pre-Socratic philosophers were from Miletus on the western coast of Anatolia. Thales (c. 624 - c. 546 BC) is reputedly the father of Greek philosophy; he declared water to be the basis of all things.[14] Next came Anaximander (610-546 BC), the first writer on philosophy. He assumed as the first principle an undefined, unlimited substance without qualities (apeiron), out of which the primary opposites, hot and cold, moist and dry, became differentiated.[14] His younger contemporary, Anaximenes (585-525 BC), took for his principle air, conceiving it as modified, by thickening and thinning, into fire, wind, clouds, water, and earth.[14]
Ephesian school
The Ephesian philosophers were interested in the natural world and the properties by which it is ordered. Xenophanes and Heraclitus were able to push philosophical inquiry further than the Milesian school by examining the nature of philosophical inquiry itself. In addition, they were also invested in furthering observations and explanations regarding natural and physical process and also the functions and processes of the human subjective experience.[19]
Heraclitus and Xenophanes both shared interests in analyzing philosophical inquiry as they contemplated morality and religious belief. This was because they wanted to figure out the proper methods of understanding human knowledge and the ways humans fit into the world. This was much different than natural philosophy that was being done by other philosophers, as it questioned the way the universe operates as well as the place of humans within it.[20]
Heraclitus posited that all things in nature are in a state of perpetual flux, connected by logical structure or pattern, which he termed Logos. To Heraclitus, fire, one of the four classical elements, motivates and substantiates this eternal pattern. From fire all things originate, and return to it again in a process of eternal cycles.
Italian school
Pythagoreanism
The practical side of philosophy was introduced by Pythagoras (582-496 BC). Regarding the world as perfect harmony, dependent on number, he aimed at inducing humankind likewise to lead a harmonious life. His doctrine was adopted and extended by a large following of Pythagoreans who gathered at his school in south Italy in the town of Croton.[14] His followers included Philolaus (470-380 BC), Alcmaeon of Croton, and Archytas (428-347 BC).
Eleatic school
According to one view, the series of thinkers located in Elea (sometimes referred to as the Eleatics, despite the fact that the precise nature of their relationships to one another is not well known) emphasized the doctrine of the One; this is often discussed in terms of the notion of monism.[21] Precisely what this means, however, is a matter for great debate.[21] Xenophanes (570-470 BC) declared a single divinity to be the eternal unity, permeating the universe, and governing it by his thought.[14] Parmenides (510-440 BC) affirmed the one unchanging existence to be alone true and capable of being conceived, and multitude and change to be an appearance without reality.[14] This doctrine was defended by his younger countryman Zeno of Elea (490-430 BC) in a polemic against the common opinion which sees in things multitude, becoming, and change. Zeno propounded a number of celebrated paradoxes, much debated by later philosophers, which try to show that supposing that there is any change or multiplicity leads to contradictions.[14] Melissus of Samos (born c. 470 BC) was another eminent member of this school.
Atomist school
The first explicitly materialistic system was formed by Leucippus (5th century BC) and his pupil Democritus (460-370 BC) from Thrace. This was the doctrine of atoms - small primary bodies infinite in number, indivisible and imperishable, qualitatively similar, but distinguished by their shapes. Moving eternally through the infinite void, they collide and unite, thus generating objects which differ in accordance with the varieties, in number, size, shape, and arrangement, of the atoms which compose them.[14]
Pluralist school
Empedocles appears to have been partly in agreement with the Eleatic School, partly in opposition to it. On the one hand, he maintained the unchangeable nature of substance; on the other, he supposes a plurality of such substances - i.e. four classical elements, earth, water, air, and fire. Of these the world is built up, by the agency of two ideal motive forces - love as the cause of union, strife as the cause of separation.[14] Anaxagoras (500-428 BC) in Asia Minor also maintained the existence of an ordering principle as well as a material substance, and while regarding the latter as an infinite multitude of imperishable primary elements, he conceived divine reason or Mind (nous) as ordering them. He referred all generation and disappearance to mixture and resolution respectively. To him belongs the credit of first establishing philosophy at Athens.[14]
Sophists
The Sophists held that all thought rests solely on the apprehensions of the senses and on subjective impression; therefore we have no other standards of action than convention for the individual.[14] Specializing in rhetoric, the Sophists were typically seen more as professional educators than philosophers. The Sophists traveled extensively educating people throughout Greece. Unlike philosophical schools, the sophists had no common set of philosophical doctrines that connected them to each other. They did, however, focus on teaching techniques of debate and persuasion which centered around the study of language, semantics, and grammar for use in convincing people of certain viewpoints. They also taught students their own interpretations of the social sciences, mathematics, history, among others.[22] They flourished as a result of a special need at that time for Greek education. Prominent Sophists include Protagoras (490-420 BC) from Abdera in Thrace, Gorgias (487-376 BC) from Leontini in Sicily, Hippias (485-415 BC) from Elis in the Peloponnesos, Prodicus (465-390 BC) from the island of Ceos, and Thrasymachus (459-400 BC) from Chalcedon on the Bosphorus.
Others
Diogenes of Apollonia from Thrace (born c. 460 BC) was an eclectic philosopher who adopted many principles of the Milesian school, especially the single material principle, which he identified as air. He explained natural processes in reference to the rarefactions and condensations of this primary substance. He also adopted Anaxagoras' cosmic thought.
Other early Greek thinkers
The first mythologoi were:
The Seven Sages of Greece (Greek: οἱ ἑπτὰ σοφοί - hoi hepta sophoi) is a title given in classical Greek tradition to a group of philosophers, statesmen, and law-givers of the 6th century BC who were renowned for their wisdom. As there is dispute about exactly who should be included, the below list shows all of those proposed as members of this group:
- Aristeas of Proconnesus (7th century BC ?)
- Periander (625–585 BC)
- Thales of Miletus (c. 620 - c. 546 BC)
- Cleobulus of Rhodes (c. 600 BC)
- Pittacus of Mitylene (c. 600 BC)
- Solon (c. 594 BC)
- Anacharsis (c. 590 BC)
- Bias of Priene (c. 570 BC)
- Chilon of Sparta (c. 560 BC)
- Pherecydes of Syros (c. 540 BC)
Legacy
- The Pre-Socratic method of critical reasoning deployed in the examination of the natural world was applied by Socrates to an examination of the human individual and his social institutions.
- Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel deeply studied the Pre-Socratics, crediting the philosopher Parmenides with introducing the concepts of Being and Non-Being (or Nothing).[23]
- Karl Marx's doctoral thesis The Difference Between the Democritean and Epicurean Philosophy of Nature evaluates the thought of the Pre-Socratic philosopher Democritus, one of the founders of Atomic theory.
- Within the Marxist philosophical tradition the Pre-Socratics are recognized as the first materialists.
- Friedrich Nietzsche described the Pre-Socratics as "the tyrants of the spirit",[24] and says of Socrates that "the hitherto so wonderfully regular, although certainly too rapid, development of the philosophical science was destroyed in one night".
- Oswald Spengler's doctoral thesis The Fundamental Metaphysical Idea of the Philosophy of Heraclitus evaluates the thought of the Pre-Socratic philosopher Heraclitus, dubbed "the obscure".
- Martin Heidegger's work after 'the turn' (die Kehre) uses the Pre-Socratic thinkers Heraclitus, and especially Parmenides, as two of his primary interlocutors.
- Karl Popper, one of the 20th century's more influential philosophers of science, placed great importance on the critical tradition embodied in the development of Pre-Socratic thought, the analysis of which contributed to his own epistemological theories. His well-known essay on the subject, "Back to the Pre-Socratics", can be found in the anthology of his essays Conjectures and Refutations - The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, 2nd Edition. Routledge Publishing. 2002.
Notes
- Presocratic Philosophy, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2007
- William Keith Chambers Guthrie, The Presocratic Tradition from Parmenides to Democritus, p. 13, ISBN 0-317-66577-4
- "Presocratic Philosophy", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 4 April 2016.
- Most, G. W. (1999). "The poetics of early Greek philosophy". In A. A. Long (Ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy (pp. 332–362). chapter, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://doi.org/10.1017/CCOL0521441226.016
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/presocratics/#WhoWerPrePhi
- Irwin, T. (1999). Classical Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, p. 6, Google Books.
- Souza, J. C. (1985). Pré-socráticos. Coleção Os Pensadores. 6ª ed. São Paulo: Nova Cultural, pp. 19, 45, PDF Archived 2016-02-22 at the Wayback Machine.
- Evans 2019, pp. 12-14.
- Franco Orsucci, Changing Mind: Transitions in Natural and Artificial Environments, p. 14, ISBN 981-238-027-2. Note: Orsucci says "Ionian and Italiote headed by Anaximander and Pythagoras", as defined by Diogenes Laërtius, quoting H Diels & K Freeman in "Ancilla to the pre-socratic philosophers" Harvard University Press 1948 - not to be confused with Italiotes, the pre-Roman Greek-speaking inhabitants of the Italian Peninsula, between Naples and Sicily
- Giannis Stamatellos, Introduction to Presocratics (2012). p. 7.
- Simon Goldhill (28 September 2006). Rethinking Revolutions Through Ancient Greece. p. 221. ISBN 9780521862127.
- The World of Parmenides, Essays on the Presocratic Enlightenment, 1998
- Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks
- Oskar Seyffert, (1894), Dictionary of Classical Antiquities, page 480
- Eduard Zeller, Outlines of the History of Greek Philosophy (1955). p. 323.
- See Farrington, Greek Science, two vols, 1953.
- American International Encyclopedia, J.J. Little Co., New York 1954, Vol VIII
- Aristotle, Metaphysics, 986b.
- Curd, Patricia (April 4, 2016). "Presocratic Philosophy". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved February 20, 2019.
- Warren, James. The Oracles of Heraclitus. Skocksfield.
- Palmer, John (2009). Parmenides & Presocratic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. see esp. 1-45.
- Hornblower, Simon. Sophists. The Oxford Classical Dictionary: Oxford University Press.
- Maybee, Julie E. (2009). Picturing Hegel: An Illustrated Guide to Hegel's Encyclopaedia of Logic. p. 46. ISBN 9780739116166.
- Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm (June 9, 2012). "The Dawn of Day". www.gutenberg.org.
References
- Brisson, L. et al. Lire les Présocratiques. Presses universitaires de France, Paris, 2012.
- Burnet, John, Early Greek Philosophy, Meridian Books, New York, 1957
- Colli, Giorgio, The Greek Wisdom (La Sapienza greca, 3 vol. Milan 1977-1980)
- De Vogel, Cornelia J., Greek Philosophy, Volume I, Thales to Plato, E.J. Brill, Leiden, 1963
- (in German) Diels, Hermann, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 6th ed., rev. by Walther Kranz (Berlin, 1952).
- (in English) Freeman, Kathleen, Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers: A Complete Translation of the Fragments in Diels, ISBN 978-1-60680-256-4 (Cambridge, [1948] 1970).
- Lloyd, G. E. R., Early Greek Science: Thales to Aristotle. New York: Norton, 1970.
- Kirk, G.S., Raven, J.E. & Schofield, M., The Presocratic Philosophers (Second Edition), Cambridge University Press, 1983
- Nahm, Milton C., Selections from Early Greek Philosophy, Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc., 1962
- (in French) Alain Sournia. Voyage en pays présocratique. Publibook, 2007.
- Giannis Stamatellos, Introduction to Presocratics: A Thematic Approach to Early Greek Philosophy with Key Readings, Wiley-Blackwell, 2012.
Further reading
- Adrados, Francisco R. 1994. "Human Vocabulary and Naturalist Vocabulary in the Presocratics." Glotta 72.1-4: 182-195.
- Cornford, F. M. 1991. From Religion to Philosophy: A Study in the Origins of Western Speculation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press.
- Graham, D. W. 2010. The Texts of Early Greek Philosophy: The Complete Fragments and Selected Testimonies of the Major Presocratics. 2 vols. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
- Franek, Juraj. 2013. "Presocratic Philosophy and the Origins of Religion." Graeco-Latina Brunensia. 18.1: 57-74.
- Furley, D. J., and R. E. Allen, eds. 1970. Studies in Presocratic Philosophy. Vol. 1, The Beginnings of Philosophy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
- Jaeger, W. 1947. The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.
- Luchte, James. 2011. Early Greek Thought: Before the Dawn. New York: Continuum
- McKirahan, R. D. 2011. Philosophy Before Socrates. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
- Popper, Karl 1998 The World of Parmenides: Essays on the Presocratic Enlightenment, Routledge
- Robb, K., ed. 1983. Language and Thought in Early Greek Philosophy. La Salle, IL: Hegeler Institute.
- Stokes, M. 1971. One and Many in Presocratic Philosophy. Washington, DC: Center for Hellenic Studies.
- Vlastos, G. 1995. Studies in Greek Philosophy. Vol. 1, The Presocratics. Edited by D. W. Graham. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press.
External links
Wikiquote has quotations related to: Pre-Socratic philosophy |
Look up Presocratic in Wiktionary, the free dictionary. |
Library resources about Pre-Socratic philosophy |
- Collections Containing Articles on Presocratic Philosophy
- Pre-Socratic philosophy at PhilPapers
- Pre-Socratic philosophy at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
- Curd, Patricia. "Presocratic Philosophy". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Graham, Jacob N. "Pre-Socratic philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Giannis Stamatellos, Presocratic Philosophy
- Chronology and geographical origins: The Ionian origins of Greek Philosophy (video).