Quantum logic

In quantum mechanics, quantum logic is a set of rules for reasoning about propositions that takes the principles of quantum theory into account. This research area and its name originated in a 1936 paper[1] by Garrett Birkhoff and John von Neumann, who were attempting to reconcile the apparent inconsistency of classical logic with the facts concerning the measurement of complementary variables in quantum mechanics, such as position and momentum.

Quantum logic can be formulated either as a modified version of propositional logic or as a noncommutative and non-associative many-valued (MV) logic.[2][3][4][5][6]

Quantum logic has been proposed as the correct logic for propositional inference generally, most notably by the philosopher Hilary Putnam, at least at one point in his career. This thesis was an important ingredient in Putnam's 1968 paper "Is Logic Empirical?" in which he analysed the epistemological status of the rules of propositional logic. Putnam attributes the idea that anomalies associated to quantum measurements originate with anomalies in the logic of physics itself to the physicist David Finkelstein. However, this idea had been around for some time and had been revived several years earlier by George Mackey's work on group representations and symmetry.

The more common view regarding quantum logic, however, is that it provides a formalism for relating observables, system preparation filters and states. In this view, the quantum logic approach resembles more closely the C*-algebraic approach to quantum mechanics. The similarities of the quantum logic formalism to a system of deductive logic may then be regarded more as a curiosity than as a fact of fundamental philosophical importance. A more modern approach to the structure of quantum logic is to assume that it is a diagram—in the sense of category theory—of classical logics (see David Edwards).

Differences with classical logic

Quantum logic has some properties that clearly distinguish it from classical logic, most notably, the failure of the distributive law of propositional logic:[7]

p and (q or r) = (p and q) or (p and r),

where the symbols p, q and r are propositional variables. To illustrate why the distributive law fails, consider a particle moving on a line and (using some system of units where the reduced Planck's constant is 1) let

p = "the particle has momentum in the interval [0, +1/6]"
q = "the particle is in the interval [−1, 1]"
r = "the particle is in the interval [1, 3]"

Note: The choice of p, q, and r in this example is intuitive but not formally valid (that is, p and (q or r) is also false here); see section "Quantum logic as the logic of observables" below for details and a valid example.

We might observe that:

p and (q or r) = true

in other words, that the particle's momentum is between 0 and +1/6, and its position is between −1 and +3. On the other hand, the propositions "p and q" and "p and r" are both false, since they assert tighter restrictions on simultaneous values of position and momentum than is allowed by the uncertainty principle (they each have uncertainty 1/3, which is less than the allowed minimum of 1/2). So,

(p and q) or (p and r) = false

Thus the distributive law fails.

Introduction

In his classic 1932 treatise Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, John von Neumann noted that projections on a Hilbert space can be viewed as propositions about physical observables. The set of principles for manipulating these quantum propositions was called quantum logic by von Neumann and Birkhoff in their 1936 paper. George Mackey, in his 1963 book (also called Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics), attempted to provide a set of axioms for this propositional system as an orthocomplemented lattice. Mackey viewed elements of this set as potential yes or no questions an observer might ask about the state of a physical system, questions that would be settled by some measurement. Moreover, Mackey defined a physical observable in terms of these basic questions. Mackey's axiom system is somewhat unsatisfactory though, since it assumes that the partially ordered set is actually given as the orthocomplemented closed subspace lattice of a separable Hilbert space. Constantin Piron, Günther Ludwig and others have attempted to give axiomatizations that do not require such explicit relations to the lattice of subspaces.

The axioms of an orthocomplemented lattice are most commonly stated as algebraic equations concerning the poset and its operations. A set of axioms using instead disjunction (denoted as ) and negation (denoted as ) is as follows:[8]

  • is commutative and associative.
  • There is a maximal element , and for any .
  • .

An orthomodular lattice satisfies the above axioms, and additionally the following one:

  • The orthomodular law: If then .

Alternative formulations include sequent calculi,[9][10][11] and tableaux systems.[12]

The remainder of this article assumes the reader is familiar with the spectral theory of self-adjoint operators on a Hilbert space. However, the main ideas can be understood using the finite-dimensional spectral theorem.

Quantum logic as the logic of observables

One semantics of quantum logic is that quantum logic is the logic of boolean observables in quantum mechanics, where an observable p is associated with the set of quantum states for which p (when measured) is true with probability 1 (this completely characterizes the observable). From there,

  • ¬p is the orthogonal complement of p (since for those states, the probability of observing p, P(p) = 0),
  • pq is the intersection of p and q, and
  • pq = ¬(¬p∧¬q) refers to states that are a superposition of p and q.

Thus, expressions in quantum logic describe observables using a syntax that resembles classical logic. However, unlike classical logic, the distributive law a ∧ (bc) = (ab) ∨ (ac) fails when dealing with noncommuting observables, such as position and momentum. This occurs because measurement affects the system, and measurement of whether a disjunction holds does not measure which of the disjuncts is true.

For an example, consider a simple one-dimensional particle with position denoted by x and momentum by p, and define observables:

  • a — |p| ≤ 1 (in some units)
  • b — x < 0
  • c — x ≥ 0

Now, position and momentum are Fourier transforms of each other, and the Fourier transform of a square-integrable nonzero function with a compact support is entire and hence does not have non-isolated zeroes. Therefore, there is no wave function that vanishes at x ≥ 0 with P(|p|≤1) = 1. Thus, ab and similarly ac are false, so (ab) ∨ (ac) is false. However, a ∧ (bc) equals a and might be true.

To understand more, let p1 and p2 be the momenta for the restriction of the particle wave function to x < 0 and x ≥ 0 respectively (with the wave function zero outside of the restriction). Let be the restriction of |p| to momenta that are (in absolute value) >1.

(ab) ∨ (ac) corresponds to states with and (this holds even if we defined p differently so as to make such states possible; also, ab corresponds to and ). As an operator, , and nonzero and might interfere to produce zero . Such interference is key to the richness of quantum logic and quantum mechanics.

The propositional lattice of a classical system

The so-called Hamiltonian formulations of classical mechanics have three ingredients: states, observables and dynamics. In the simplest case of a single particle moving in R3, the state space is the position-momentum space R6. We will merely note here that an observable is some real-valued function f on the state space. Examples of observables are position, momentum or energy of a particle. For classical systems, the value f(x), that is the value of f for some particular system state x, is obtained by a process of measurement of f. The propositions concerning a classical system are generated from basic statements of the form

"Measurement of f yields a value in the interval [a, b] for some real numbers a, b."

It follows easily from this characterization of propositions in classical systems that the corresponding logic is identical to that of some Boolean algebra of subsets of the state space. By logic in this context we mean the rules that relate set operations and ordering relations, such as de Morgan's laws. These are analogous to the rules relating boolean conjunctives and material implication in classical propositional logic. For technical reasons, we will also assume that the algebra of subsets of the state space is that of all Borel sets. The set of propositions is ordered by the natural ordering of sets and has a complementation operation. In terms of observables, the complement of the proposition {fa} is {f < a}.

We summarize these remarks as follows: The proposition system of a classical system is a lattice with a distinguished orthocomplementation operation: The lattice operations of meet and join are respectively set intersection and set union. The orthocomplementation operation is set complement. Moreover, this lattice is sequentially complete, in the sense that any sequence {Ei}i of elements of the lattice has a least upper bound, specifically the set-theoretic union:

The propositional lattice of a quantum mechanical system

In the Hilbert space formulation of quantum mechanics as presented by von Neumann, a physical observable is represented by some (possibly unbounded) densely defined self-adjoint operator A on a Hilbert space H. A has a spectral decomposition, which is a projection-valued measure E defined on the Borel subsets of R. In particular, for any bounded Borel function f on R, the following extension of f to operators can be made:

In case f is the indicator function of an interval [a, b], the operator f(A) is a self-adjoint projection, and can be interpreted as the quantum analogue of the classical proposition

  • Measurement of A yields a value in the interval [a, b].

This suggests the following quantum mechanical replacement for the orthocomplemented lattice of propositions in classical mechanics. This is essentially Mackey's Axiom VII:

  • The orthocomplemented lattice Q of propositions of a quantum mechanical system is the lattice of closed subspaces of a complex Hilbert space H where orthocomplementation of V is the orthogonal complement V.

Q is also sequentially complete: any pairwise disjoint sequence{Vi}i of elements of Q has a least upper bound. Here disjointness of W1 and W2 means W2 is a subspace of W1. The least upper bound of {Vi}i is the closed internal direct sum.

Henceforth we identify elements of Q with self-adjoint projections on the Hilbert space H.

The structure of Q immediately points to a difference with the partial order structure of a classical proposition system. In the classical case, given a proposition p, the equations

have exactly one solution, namely the set-theoretic complement of p. In these equations I refers to the atomic proposition that is identically true and 0 the atomic proposition that is identically false. In the case of the lattice of projections there are infinitely many solutions to the above equations (any closed, algebraic complement of p solves it; it need not be the orthocomplement).

Having made these preliminary remarks, we turn everything around and attempt to define observables within the projection lattice framework and using this definition establish the correspondence between self-adjoint operators and observables: A Mackey observable is a countably additive homomorphism from the orthocomplemented lattice of the Borel subsets of R to Q. To say the mapping φ is a countably additive homomorphism means that for any sequence {Si}i of pairwise disjoint Borel subsets of R, {φ(Si)}i are pairwise orthogonal projections and

Effectively, then, a Mackey observable is a projection-valued measure on R.

Theorem. There is a bijective correspondence between Mackey observables and densely defined self-adjoint operators on H.

This is the content of the spectral theorem as stated in terms of spectral measures.

Statistical structure

Imagine a forensics lab that has some apparatus to measure the speed of a bullet fired from a gun. Under carefully controlled conditions of temperature, humidity, pressure and so on the same gun is fired repeatedly and speed measurements taken. This produces some distribution of speeds. Though we will not get exactly the same value for each individual measurement, for each cluster of measurements, we would expect the experiment to lead to the same distribution of speeds. In particular, we can expect to assign probability distributions to propositions such as {a ≤ speed ≤ b}. This leads naturally to propose that under controlled conditions of preparation, the measurement of a classical system can be described by a probability measure on the state space. This same statistical structure is also present in quantum mechanics.

A quantum probability measure is a function P defined on Q with values in [0,1] such that P(0)=0, P(I)=1 and if {Ei}i is a sequence of pairwise orthogonal elements of Q then

The following highly non-trivial theorem is due to Andrew Gleason:

Theorem. Suppose Q is a separable Hilbert space of complex dimension at least 3. Then for any quantum probability measure P on Q there exists a unique trace class operator S such that

for any self-adjoint projection E in Q.

The operator S is necessarily non-negative (that is all eigenvalues are non-negative) and of trace 1. Such an operator is often called a density operator.

Physicists commonly regard a density operator as being represented by a (possibly infinite) density matrix relative to some orthonormal basis.

For more information on statistics of quantum systems, see quantum statistical mechanics.

Automorphisms

An automorphism of Q is a bijective mapping α:QQ that preserves the orthocomplemented structure of Q, that is

for any sequence {Ei}i of pairwise orthogonal self-adjoint projections. Note that this property implies monotonicity of α. If P is a quantum probability measure on Q, then E → α(E) is also a quantum probability measure on Q. By the Gleason theorem characterizing quantum probability measures quoted above, any automorphism α induces a mapping α* on the density operators by the following formula:

The mapping α* is bijective and preserves convex combinations of density operators. This means

whenever 1 = r1 + r2 and r1, r2 are non-negative real numbers. Now we use a theorem of Richard V. Kadison:

Theorem. Suppose β is a bijective map from density operators to density operators that is convexity preserving. Then there is an operator U on the Hilbert space that is either linear or conjugate-linear, preserves the inner product and is such that

for every density operator S. In the first case we say U is unitary, in the second case U is anti-unitary.

Remark. This note is included for technical accuracy only, and should not concern most readers. The result quoted above is not directly stated in Kadison's paper, but can be reduced to it by noting first that β extends to a positive trace preserving map on the trace class operators, then applying duality and finally applying a result of Kadison's paper.

The operator U is not quite unique; if r is a complex scalar of modulus 1, then r U will be unitary or anti-unitary if U is and will implement the same automorphism. In fact, this is the only ambiguity possible.

It follows that automorphisms of Q are in bijective correspondence to unitary or anti-unitary operators modulo multiplication by scalars of modulus 1. Moreover, we can regard automorphisms in two equivalent ways: as operating on states (represented as density operators) or as operating on Q.

Non-relativistic dynamics

In non-relativistic physical systems, there is no ambiguity in referring to time evolution since there is a global time parameter. Moreover, an isolated quantum system evolves in a deterministic way: if the system is in a state S at time t then at time s > t, the system is in a state Fs,t(S). Moreover, we assume

  • The dependence is reversible: The operators Fs,t are bijective.
  • The dependence is homogeneous: Fs,t = Fs  t,0.
  • The dependence is convexity preserving: That is, each Fs,t(S) is convexity preserving.
  • The dependence is weakly continuous: The mapping RR given by t → Tr(Fs,t(S) E) is continuous for every E in Q.

By Kadison's theorem, there is a 1-parameter family of unitary or anti-unitary operators {Ut}t such that

In fact,

Theorem. Under the above assumptions, there is a strongly continuous 1-parameter group of unitary operators {Ut}t such that the above equation holds.

Note that it follows easily from uniqueness from Kadison's theorem that

where σ(t,s) has modulus 1. Now the square of an anti-unitary is a unitary, so that all the Ut are unitary. The remainder of the argument shows that σ(t,s) can be chosen to be 1 (by modifying each Ut by a scalar of modulus 1.)

Pure states

A convex combination of statistical states S1 and S2 is a state of the form S = p1 S1 +p2 S2 where p1, p2 are non-negative and p1 + p2 =1. Considering the statistical state of system as specified by lab conditions used for its preparation, the convex combination S can be regarded as the state formed in the following way: toss a biased coin with outcome probabilities p1, p2 and depending on outcome choose system prepared to S1 or S2

Density operators form a convex set. The convex set of density operators has extreme points; these are the density operators given by a projection onto a one-dimensional space. To see that any extreme point is such a projection, note that by the spectral theorem S can be represented by a diagonal matrix; since S is non-negative all the entries are non-negative and since S has trace 1, the diagonal entries must add up to 1. Now if it happens that the diagonal matrix has more than one non-zero entry it is clear that we can express it as a convex combination of other density operators.

The extreme points of the set of density operators are called pure states. If S is the projection on the 1-dimensional space generated by a vector ψ of norm 1 then

for any E in Q. In physics jargon, if

where ψ has norm 1, then

Thus pure states can be identified with rays in the Hilbert space H.

The measurement process

Consider a quantum mechanical system with lattice Q that is in some statistical state given by a density operator S. This essentially means an ensemble of systems specified by a repeatable lab preparation process. The result of a cluster of measurements intended to determine the truth value of proposition E, is just as in the classical case, a probability distribution of truth values T and F. Say the probabilities are p for T and q = 1  p for F. By the previous section p = Tr(S E) and q = Tr(S (I  E)).

Perhaps the most fundamental difference between classical and quantum systems is the following: regardless of what process is used to determine E immediately after the measurement the system will be in one of two statistical states:

  • If the result of the measurement is T
  • If the result of the measurement is F

(We leave to the reader the handling of the degenerate cases in which the denominators may be 0.) We now form the convex combination of these two ensembles using the relative frequencies p and q. We thus obtain the result that the measurement process applied to a statistical ensemble in state S yields another ensemble in statistical state:

We see that a pure ensemble becomes a mixed ensemble after measurement. Measurement, as described above, is a special case of quantum operations.

Limitations

Quantum logic derived from propositional logic provides a satisfactory foundation for a theory of reversible quantum processes. Examples of such processes are the covariance transformations relating two frames of reference, such as change of time parameter or the transformations of special relativity. Quantum logic also provides a satisfactory understanding of density matrices. Quantum logic can be stretched to account for some kinds of measurement processes corresponding to answering yes–no questions about the state of a quantum system. However, for more general kinds of measurement operations (that is quantum operations), a more complete theory of filtering processes is necessary. Such a theory of quantum filtering was developed in the late 1970s and 1980s by Belavkin [13][14] (see also Bouten et al.[15]). A similar approach is provided by the consistent histories formalism. On the other hand, quantum logics derived from many-valued logic extend its range of applicability to irreversible quantum processes or 'open' quantum systems.

In any case, these quantum logic formalisms must be generalized in order to deal with super-geometry (which is needed to handle Fermi-fields) and non-commutative geometry (which is needed in string theory and quantum gravity theory). Both of these theories use a partial algebra with an "integral" or "trace". The elements of the partial algebra are not observables; instead the "trace" yields "greens functions", which generate scattering amplitudes. One thus obtains a local S-matrix theory (see D. Edwards).

In 2004, Prakash Panangaden described how to capture the kinematics of quantum causal evolution using System BV, a deep inference logic originally developed for use in structural proof theory.[16] Alessio Guglielmi, Lutz Straßburger, and Richard Blute have also done work in this area.[17]

See also

References

  1. Birkhoff, Garrett; von Neumann, John (1936). "The Logic of Quantum Mechanics" (PDF). Annals of Mathematics. Second Series. 37 (4): 823–843. doi:10.2307/1968621. JSTOR 1968621.
  2. https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0101028v2 Maria Luisa Dalla Chiara and Roberto Giuntini. 2008. Quantum Logics, 102 pages PDF
  3. Dalla Chiara, M. L.; Giuntini, R. (1994). "Unsharp quantum logics". Foundations of Physics. 24: 1161–1177. Bibcode:1994FoPh...24.1161D. doi:10.1007/bf02057862. S2CID 122872424.
  4. http://planetphysics.org/encyclopedia/QuantumLMAlgebraicLogic.html%5B%5D I. C. Baianu. 2009. Quantum LMn Algebraic Logic.
  5. Georgescu, G.; Vraciu, C. (1970). "On the characterization of centered Łukasiewicz algebras". J. Algebra. 16 (4): 486–495. doi:10.1016/0021-8693(70)90002-5.
  6. Georgescu, G (2006). "N-valued Logics and Łukasiewicz-Moisil Algebras". Axiomathes. 16 (1–2): 123. doi:10.1007/s10516-005-4145-6. S2CID 121264473.
  7. "Quantum logic" entry by Peter Forrest in the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 7 (1998), p. 882ff: "[Quantum logic] differs from the standard sentential calculus ... The most notable difference is that the distributive laws fail, being replaced by a weaker law known as orthomodularity."
  8. Megill, Norman. "Quantum Logic Explorer". Metamath. Retrieved 2019-07-12.
  9. N.J. Cutland; P.F. Gibbins (Sep 1982). "A regular sequent calculus for Quantum Logic in which ∨ and ∧ are dual". Logique et Analyse. Nouvelle Série. 25 (99): 221–248. JSTOR 44084050.
  10. Hirokazu Nishimura (Jan 1994). "Proof theory for minimal quantum logic I". International Journal of Theoretical Physics. 33 (1): 103–113. Bibcode:1994IJTP...33..103N. doi:10.1007/BF00671616. S2CID 123183879.
  11. Hirokazu Nishimura (Jul 1994). "Proof theory for minimal quantum logic II". International Journal of Theoretical Physics. 33 (7): 1427–1443. Bibcode:1994IJTP...33.1427N. doi:10.1007/bf00670687. S2CID 189850106.
  12. Uwe Egly; Hans Tompits (1999). "Gentzen-like Methods in Quantum Logic" (PDF). Proc. 8th Int. Conf. on Automated Reasoning with Analytic Tableaux and Related Methods (TABLEAUX). University at Albany SUNY. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.88.9045.
  13. V. P. Belavkin (1978). "Optimal quantum filtration of Makovian signals [In Russian]". Problems of Control and Information Theory. 7 (5): 345–360.
  14. V. P. Belavkin (1992). "Quantum stochastic calculus and quantum nonlinear filtering". Journal of Multivariate Analysis. 42 (2): 171–201. arXiv:math/0512362. doi:10.1016/0047-259X(92)90042-E. S2CID 3909067.
  15. Luc Bouten; Ramon van Handel; Matthew R. James (2009). "A discrete invitation to quantum filtering and feedback control". SIAM Review. 51 (2): 239–316. arXiv:math/0606118. Bibcode:2009SIAMR..51..239B. doi:10.1137/060671504. S2CID 10435983.
  16. http://cs.bath.ac.uk/ag/p/BVQuantCausEvol.pdf
  17. "DI & CoS - Current Research Topics and Open Problems". alessio.guglielmi.name.

Further reading

  • S. Auyang, How is Quantum Field Theory Possible?, Oxford University Press, 1995.
  • F. Bayen, M. Flato, C. Fronsdal, A. Lichnerowicz and D. Sternheimer, Deformation theory and quantization I, II, Ann. Phys. (N.Y.), 111 (1978) pp. 61–110, 111–151.
  • G. Birkhoff and J. von Neumann, *The Logic of Quantum Mechanics, Annals of Mathematics, Vol. 37, pp. 823–843, 1936.
  • D. Cohen, An Introduction to Hilbert Space and Quantum Logic, Springer-Verlag, 1989. This is a thorough but elementary and well-illustrated introduction, suitable for advanced undergraduates.
  • M.L. Dalla Chiara. R. Giuntini, G. Sergioli, "Probability in quantum computation and in quantum computational logics" . Mathematical Structures in Computer Sciences, ISSN 0960-1295, Vol.24, Issue 3, Cambridge University Press (2014).
  • David Edwards, The Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Synthese, Volume 42, Number 1/September, 1979, pp. 1–70.
  • D. Edwards, The Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Field Theory: Fermions, Gauge Fields, and Super-symmetry, Part I: Lattice Field Theories, International J. of Theor. Phys., Vol. 20, No. 7 (1981).
  • D. Finkelstein, Matter, Space and Logic, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol. V, 1969
  • A. Gleason, Measures on the Closed Subspaces of a Hilbert Space, Journal of Mathematics and Mechanics, 1957.
  • R. Kadison, Isometries of Operator Algebras, Annals of Mathematics, Vol. 54, pp. 325–338, 1951
  • G. Ludwig, Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Springer-Verlag, 1983.
  • G. Mackey, Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, W. A. Benjamin, 1963 (paperback reprint by Dover 2004).
  • J. von Neumann, Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Princeton University Press, 1955. Reprinted in paperback form.
  • R. Omnès, Understanding Quantum Mechanics, Princeton University Press, 1999. An extraordinarily lucid discussion of some logical and philosophical issues of quantum mechanics, with careful attention to the history of the subject. Also discusses consistent histories.
  • N. Papanikolaou, Reasoning Formally About Quantum Systems: An Overview, ACM SIGACT News, 36(3), pp. 51–66, 2005.
  • C. Piron, Foundations of Quantum Physics, W. A. Benjamin, 1976.
  • H. Putnam, Is Logic Empirical?, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol. V, 1969
  • H. Weyl, The Theory of Groups and Quantum Mechanics, Dover Publications, 1950.
This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.